Incumbent performance and electoral control - Ed Egan

2 downloads 61 Views 867KB Size Report
platforms of the candidates and vote for the one whose platform is ... use their initiative in the face of new or unexpected events that arise ..... We can now state our major results. .... New. Key, V. (1966) The Responsible Electorate. New York: Vintage Books. ... (1971) Short Term Fluctuations in U.S. Voting Behavior, 1896-.
Public Choice 50:5-25 (1986). © 1986 Martinus N i j h o f f Publishers, Dordrecht. Printed in the Netherlands.

Incumbent performance and electoral control

JOHN FEREJOHN*

I.

INTRODUCTION

In the pure theory of

electoral

competition, citizens compare the

platforms of the candidates and vote for the one whose platform is preferred.

Candidate strategies

future performance in office.

are identified

with promises about

Models of this sort have been developed

in both static [McKelvey (1975)] and dynamic [Kramer (1977)I settings, and all appear to have the property that i f the set of alternatives is "large enough" in some sense, equilibrium platforms rarely exist.

But

these models have another feature that is quite as disturbing as their instability. In the static setting discussed by McKelvey, l i t t l e attention

is

paid to the possibility that, once in office, the politician's preferences may diverge from those of his constituents

and that he may

therefore choose policies at variance from his platform.

Instead i t is

simply assumed that promises will be kept whether or not such behavior is congruent with the interest of the officeholder.

I t is sometimes

argued that an "enforcement" mechanism may exist to discipline politicians for failing to keep promises, but without a specification of the mechanism i t is not obvious that i t would be in the interests of the

tSenior Research Fellow at the Hoover I n s t i t u t i o n and Professor of P o l i t i c a l Science at Stanford U n i v e r s i t y . Special thanks are due t o David Baron, Joseph Greenberg, Tom P a l f r e y , and Tom Romer f o r c a r e f u l reading and c r i t i c i s m of e a r l i e r v e r s i o n s of t h i s paper.

electorate to carry out threatened punishments. In Kramer's dynamic model, the incumbent's platform is identified with his current record in office so that, assuming that voters would believe any proposed platform,

a challenger will

able to propose a platform that will incumbent knows that he w i l l

v i r t u a l l y always be

defeat the incumbent. But i f the

lose his reelection bid, he might as well

simply pursue his own private interest while in office rather than doing what he promised during the campaign (or doing whatever he did during his previous term); he will Clearly,

in this

be turned out at the next election anyway.

case, the voters have no reason to take challenger

platforms as anything other than pure rhetoric; voters would soon learn that

rational

officeholders

would ignore

their

preferences

once in

office. In both of these cases, there is no reason for voters to pay attention to the candidates'

choice of platforms.

is no cause to believe that there w i l l

For this reason, there

be any predictable connection

between the profile of voter preferences and public policy.

I f there

actually is such a connection, neither of these theories can account for it. The pure theory of elections pays l i t t l e

attention to the sorts of

strategies or decision rules that might be followed by members of the electorate.

Instead, i t is usually hypothesized that citizens vote for

the candidate whose platform they like best, ignoring further strategic considerations.

Indeed, in two-candidate

contest,

if

candidates are

assumed to implement their platforms, voting for someone other than the preferred candidate

is

a dominated strategy.

The only interesting

question in this case is whether or not to vote. The purpose of this paper is to try to construct a coherent model in which voters have an incentive to base t h e i r choices on behavior of officeholders and in which officeholders choose their anticipation of this behavior.

strategies

in

Such a model is necessarily dynamic.

Voters are assumed to base t h e i r evaluations of officeholders on t h e i r actual performance in office rather than on hypothetical promises they might make during a campaign.

In this model, the key to the voting

decision is found not in the earnest pledges of the contenders but, rather, in the infamous remark of a Kansas farmer: done For me lately?"

"But what have you

I f voters vote on the basis of platforms or "issues," p o l i t i c i a n s have l i t t l e

incentive to do what they promise.

Thus, voters might be

well-advised to pay attention to the incumbent's performance rather than to the hypothetical

in office

promises of competing candidates.

By

basing t h e i r votes on evaluations of performance, voters may be able to motivate

officeholders

electors.

That

to

pay

attention

such a strategy

f o r c e f u l l y argued by V.O. Key (1966). or punish officeholders officeholders

will

of

the

has been most

but w i l l

in o f f i c e ,

also be motivated to

in the face of new or unexpected events that arise empirical

elections

only a partial

nomena.

interests

on the basis of t h e i r performance

between elections. There is abundant is,

the

Key argued that i f voters reward

not only be d i l i g e n t

use t h e i r i n i t i a t i v e

to

may be a t t r a c t i v e

at best,

evidence

that

the

description

Much of recent data suggest that

pure theory

of electoral

of phe-

voters do respond to the

performance of incumbent candidates in office as well as to the platform promises of competing

candidates

[Kramer (1971), Fiorina

both the aggregate and individual that

have been studied,

effect there

on the electoral is

evidence that

level

(1981)I.

and in v i r t u a l l y

the performance

all

try

nations

of the economy has a major

fate of the incumbent executive. officeholders

At

to

anticipate

Moreover, performance-

oriented voting in t h e i r choice of policies while in o f f i c e . I Thus, i t appears that voters employ decision rules that are based, in part, on the past performance of the government in o f f i c e .

Moreover,

the actual evidence for extensive issue voting is f a i r l y weak. incumbent

administration has

been successful

growth and avoiding major wars,

it

will

in

promoting

I f the economic

tend to be rewarded at the

polls, no matter how a t t r a c t i v e the policy positions of the opposition. 2 This paper begins an investigation of the structure of electoral

ISee the poiltical business-cycle literature, especially Tufte (1978), Recent work on Congress [Mayhew (1974)] suggests that similar incentives structure the behavior of Congressmen. 21n splte'of the great quantity of statistical investigations of issue voting, the evidence for effects of candidate platforms on the vote is mixed. See Page and Jones (1979).

behavior that takes account of the motivations

of o f f i c e h o l d e r s .

We

wish to know how voters ought to behave i f they wish to get t h e i r representatives to pursue the interests of the e l e c t o r s . this

question,

ticians

we need to develop a formal

In order to address

model within which p o l i -

can be induced to act in the i n t e r e s t s

of the electors.

The

natural mechanism to transmit such incentives is the fact that elections take place repeatedly and that officeholders

desire to r e t a i n o f f i c e .

Under these circumstances, voters can adopt strategies that can a f f e c t the incentives

of o f f i c e h o l d e r s

in various

ways.

separating the actions of the candidates in o f f i c e the performance of date.

With t h i s

"principal-agent" electors, facing

a government which separation,

is

insist

on

from the notion of

led by an incumbent candi-

the s i t u a t i o n

becomes a variant

problem in which the o f f i c e h o l d e r

and voters

We also

of the

is an agent of the

have the opportunity to structure the incentives

the o f f i c e h o l d e r

agent to

induce him to act to enhance t h e i r

well-being. The paper introduces an a l t e r n a t i v e theory of e l e c t i o n s , as pure in i t s own way as the classical

one exposited by McKelvey and Kramer.

In

t h i s model voters respond only to the performance of the candidate in office

and do not pay any a t t e n t i o n whatsoever to the promises of the

challenger or, f o r that matter, to the promises of the incumbent.

All

that counts f o r a voter here is how well he fares under a given administration. In the model, voters assume that a newly elected o f f i c e h o l d e r w i l l pursue his own i n t e r e s t s once in o f f i c e , the context of the campaign. because there them. that

is

On t h i s view, promises play no role at a l l

no way f o r

As long as p o l i t i c i a n s they

have the

correctly anticipate

no matter what he claimed in

candidates to commit themselves to keep are a l l

same preferences

of the same "type," in the sense and a b i l i t i e s ,

how the o f f i c e h o l d e r w i l l

stance that may confront

him.

the

voter

can

behave in every circum-

No promise to do otherwise would be

credible and so none would be heeded. Given t h i s hypothesis about the behavior of p o l i t i c i a n s

in o f f i c e ,

the voters w i l l

choose a decision rule that maximizes t h e i r well-being

subject

constraint

interest.

to the

Nevertheless,

that voters

politicians

are pursuing t h e i r

are constrained

in

their

self-

choice of

decision rules to recognize that at any future time, prescribed voting

behavior must be in the i n t e r e s t of the electors at that time.

They are

unable to bind or precommit themselves or t h e i r o f f s p r i n g to choices in the future that w i l l rules

seem u n a t t r a c t i v e at that time.

based on " i n c r e d i b l e "

threats

Thus, those voting

are not available

because o f f i c e -

holders would recognize that such threats would not be carried out.

2.

PREVIOUS RESEARCH

There has been some investigation of the incentives that certain types of

performance-oriented

(1975)}. myopic,

rules

confer

on incumbents

[Nordhaus

However, most of this work focuses on a r e l a t i v e l y specialized

implication years

voting

of performance-oriented voting:

i f voters are s u f f i c i e n t l y

incumbents have an incentive to behave d i f f e r e n t l y than at

other

business cycles.

times

and therefore

to t r y

in e l e c t i o n

to create p o l i t i c a l

Whether or not incumbents are able to create p o l i t i c a l

business cycles, however, depends on a v a r i e t y of other factors i r r e l e vant to our present concern with the control choice of voter-decision rules.

of incumbents through the

Indeed, recent work suggests that

voters are able to take account of economic constraints, induced business

cycles

Moreover, the formulation

may not

occur

of p o l i t i c a l

[Chappell

if

politically-

and Keech (1985)].

business-cycle models does not

pay much a t t e n t i o n to the choice of optimal voter-decision rules, given the opportunities of incumbents. More relevant to the present paper is Robert Barro's (1973) seminal investigation

of

the control

of p o l i t i c i a n s .

Barro investigates

the

question of how much the f a c t of repeated elections may induce o f f i c e holders to act on the preferences of the electorate rather than t h e i r own objectives. spects.

Barro's

approach d i f f e r s

from ours

in

F i r s t , he assumes that o f f i c e h o l d e r s have a f i n i t e

known horizon.

Thus, in

their

last

several

re-

and commonly

term of o f f i c e t h e i r behavior is

10

uncontrollable. 3

In light

of this

uncontrollability,

the electorate

would not return an officeholder seeking his last term; the p o l i t i c i a n would then see this and be uncontrollable in the penultimate term, and the process would unravel.

The present model is formulated with an

i n f i n i t e horizon, so that such last-period effects are avoided.

The

reader may think of the competitors for office as p o l i t i c a l parties that last

indefinitely and must solve the "last-period" problem for their

officeholders through the use of internal incentives. 4 Second, Barro's model is formulated

in a world of perfect infor-

mation, whereas the present model contains an informational asymmetry: the electorate is not able to observe the actions of politicians directly.

With perfect information the voter is able to extract most of

the rents

in the transaction.

In equilibrium,

at each period,

the

electorate demands that the officeholder provide a quantity of e f f o r t that leaves him indifferent between leaving and staying in office.

Here

we allow a natural informational asymmetry in favor of o f f i c i a l s , which allows

them opportunities

sitions. officials

Intuitively,

to take advantage of their privileged po-

the greater the informational

advantage that

hold, the greater t h e i r a b i l i t y to earn rents from o f f i c e -

holding. Finally,

Barro's model contains only one "representative" voter.

In effect, this formulation assumes not only that voter preferences are identical,

an assumption that may in some circumstances be j u s t i f i e d ,

but also that there are no distributional competition,

issues at stake in p o l i t i c a l

surely a more controversial

hypothesis.

W h i l e we are

unable to provide a complete analysis of the general case, we do show that the introduction of distributional

issues profoundly changes the

nature of the relationship between the electorate and its o f f i c i a l s , vastly reducing the level of electoral control.

3The mechanism suggested t o overcome the l a s t - p e r i o d problem is the one introduced by Becker and S t i g l e r (1974)o Becker and S t i g l e r argue t h a t misbehavior can be c o n t r o l l e d i f o f f i c e h o l d e r s face the loss of a pension ( o r , e q u i v a l e n t l y , a posted bond) in the event of malfeasance in their last term, Barro suggests that political parties might offer future appointment t o o f f i c e as an inducement f o r good l a s t - p e r i o d performance. 4See previous note.

ii

In the next section we o u t l i n e a simple dynamic model of e l e c t o r a l competition that allows us to analyze the incentives of o f f i c e h o l d e r s and to see how they would respond to v a r i a t i o n s in e l e c t o r a l behavior. This model, electorate)

like

Barro's,

contains only one voter

and two or more candidates.

(or a homogeneous

The "space" over which the

performance of the o f f i c e h o l d e r is defined is i d e n t i f i e d with an i n t e r val

on the

real

line.

In t h i s

dimensional outcome space is

context,

the r e s t r i c t i o n

to a one-

inconsequential, though in other settings

i t may not be. When we turn our a t t e n t i o n to a model in which there are several voters, the s i t u a t i o n changes s u b s t a n t i a l l y .

In Section 4 we show that

the introduction of preference d i v e r s i t y permits the incumbent to escape electoral

control

aggregate voting.

unless the voters

performance

index

I f voters u t i l i z e

incumbent w i l l advantage.

as

"agree" to u t i l i z e

their

criterion

for

some sort

of

retrospective

i n d i v i d u a l i s t i c or group-based c r i t e r i a ,

the

have the opportunity to e x p l o i t voter d i v i s i o n s to his

The nature of such an agreement does not e n t a i l any precom-

mitments by the voters, in the sense of requiring anyone to vote against his

or

her

interests

at

some future

agreement would be c r e d i b l e . that

electoral

control

point

in time,

and so such an

We may i n t e r p r e t t h i s r e s u l t as saying

with

a

nonhomogeneous electorate

requires

" s o c i o t r o p i c " voting - - that i s , voting based on an aggregate c r i t e r i o n - - rather than i n d i v i d u a l i s t i c voting [Kiewiet (1983)I.

3.

A SIMPLE MODELOF REPEATED ELECTIONS WITH A HOMOGENEOUS ELECTORATE

Many of the a c t i v i t i e s of o f f i c e h o l d e r s are not d i r e c t l y observable by members of the e l e c t o r a t e . the

effects

Further,

of

governmental

governmental

activities

Instead, electors are only able to assess performance

performance

is

of officeholders as well

essentially probabilistic factors. an agent of

on

known to

their

own well-being.

depend j o i n t l y

on the

as on a v a r i e t y of exogenous and In other words, the o f f i c e h o l d e r is

the electorate whose behavior is

imperfectly monitored.

Officeholders are assumed to desire r e e l e c t i o n

in order to take ad-

vantage of

the perquisites of o f f i c e

ideas about p o l i c y .

as well

as to pursue t h e i r

own

I t is the desire to r e t a i n o f f i c e together with the

12

p o s s i b i l i t y of an indirect monitoring by the electorate which drive the incentive effects that we observe in the model. Before setting out the model, we should emphasize that we have assumed that candidates for office are a l l essentially the same in the sense that they have the same preferences and a b i l i t i e s , and that this is common knowledge among a l l the actors.

In other words, the voter's

problem is to police moral hazard rather than to find and elect the more capable of ~benevolent officeholders.

Rules of the sort we are ad-

dressing here may have the property of separating different types of officeholders in an appropriate

setting, but we do not address those

aspects here. In

this

functional

paper we take

the

liberty

of

working with

Forms that are r e l a t i v e l y easy to analyze.

explicit

Some of the

arguments developed here might be generalized in other settings, but for now we have chosen to t r y to obtain clear results in the context of a very simple model in order to aid our i n t u i t i o n about the ways in which the behavior of electors might induce officeholders to pay attention to their preferences. The officeholder observes a random variable, e ~ ~ = [0, m], a subset of the nonnegative real numbers, and then takes an action, a [0,~), conditioned on that observation.

We l e t F denote the d i s t r i -

bution

it

Function

entiable.

of

e and assume that

is

continuously

differ-

The single-period preferences of the officeholder are written

as v(a,e)

= w -

~(a),

where W is the value of holding office for a single term and ¢ is a positive monotone convex function and ¢(0) = O.

W may be thought of as

the e x p l i c i t compensation of the officeholder plus any rents he may earn as a result of his tenure and ¢(a) is the cost of action a. The voter is unable to distinguish the actions of the officeholder from exogenous occurrences. Rather than d i r e c t l y observing "policy," he is restricted to monitoring product

of

"performance," which is defined to be a

policy and exogenous occurrences.

single-period preferences are represented as

T h u s , the elector's

13

u(a,e) = ae. Lacking an a b i l i t y

to observe the a c t i v i t i e s

e l e c t o r adopts a simple performance-oriented rule:

if

the u t i l i t y

office

is

high enough,

of the incumbent, the

(or retrospective)

voting

received at the end of the incumbent's term in he votes to

return

the

incumbent to o f f i c e ;

otherwise he removes the incumbent and gives the job to someone else. I t is clear that,

under certain conditions,

such a rule w i l l

induce the

incumbent to pay a t t e n t i o n to the requirements of retaining o f f i c e . is

also clear

utility will

that

the elector

level appropriately,

not find

it

must be careful

since i f

it

to

It

set the required

is set too high the incumbent

worthwhile to t r y to r e t a i n o f f i c e

and w i l l

instead

choose to take advantage of the opportunities c u r r e n t l y available to him as an o f f i c e h o l d e r . incumbent w i l l

On the other hand, i f the level is set too low, the

find

it

o f f i c e that he w i l l It will

sufficiently

easy to sustain his hold on the

choose too low a level of a.

turn out that the incumbent's behavior depends c r i t i c a l l y

on his l i k e l i h o o d of being able to return to o f f i c e in the future in the event that he is defeated. polar cases:

(i)

In the following analysis we consider two

in the event of a loss of o f f i c e , the incumbent has no

chance of returning;

(2)

in the event of a loss of o f f i c e ,

the in-

cumbent is replaced by another agent and returns to o f f i c e i f and when that

other agent loses.

We think of the f i r s t

assumption as corre-

sponding more or less to multiparty competition with small p a r t i e s , which a party out of o f f i c e gaining i t quite

final

system.

has a r e l a t i v e l y

at the next e l e c t i o n . from

This

the

also

small p r o b a b i l i t y of re-

The loss o f - o f f i c e would appear to be

standpoint

case could

in

of

the

incumbent

party

model the candidate's

in

such

perspective

a as

opposed to the party perspective in two-party system in which the comp e t i t o r s are party "teams" that a l t e r n a t e in o f f i c e . Several remarks about t h i s formulation seem important. model contains an extreme informational ficial

is

while

the

somewhat,

able to voter

resolve a l l

cannot.

we could

uncertainty

At the

introduce

asymmetry.

cost

of

an additional

First,

the

The incumbent o f -

before taking complicating disturbance

his the

action, notation

representing

uncertainty that the candidate is unable to resolve p r i o r to his choice of

policy.

In

this

case,

the

candidate

would

view

his

election

14

prospects as uncertain.

While t h i s case is perhaps more r e a l i s t i c ,

does not permit us to gain any additional

it

insights into e i t h e r incumbent

or voter strategies. Both o f f i c i a l s

and voters are assumed to be r i s k

neutral.

This

assumption s i m p l i f i e s the analysis somewhat and also a f f e c t s the nature of optimal strategies.

I f the candidate and voter d i f f e r

aversion, issues related to risk sharing would arise. cases may be more r e a l i s t i c ,

they

would

in t h e i r r i s k

Again, while such

needlessly

complicate

the

present analysis and so we leave them aside. F i n a l l y , for reasons alluded to in the introduction,

the challenger

plays no active role in the model.

The importance of challengers l i e s

entirely

availability.

It

gives

whatever leverage

in

their

officeseekers incumbent.

that

the voter

is

the

existence

of

willing

he has on the

For this reason, i t is important that the e l e c t i v e o f f i c e is

valuable enough r e l a t i v e to a l t e r n a t i v e sources of employment to a t t r a c t challengers. Given the one-period preferences outlined above, and assuming that the elector employs a retrospective voting r u l e , we can u t i l i z e techniques of dynamic programming havior.

to determine optimal

standard

candidate

Once the incumbent has observed a value of et, he w i l l

an action

which

maximizes

his

(discounted)

utility

from

be-

choose

that

time

onward, assuming that the voter employs a retrospective voting rule with cutoff

levels,

Kt ,

Kt+l,

Kt+ 2 . . . . .

from time t

forward.

Under the

conditions assumed above, t h i s amounts to choosing a(et) to maximize t h e present value of u t i l i t y

stream.

Obviously,

if

is not possible to be reelected, then he w i l l

et is so small that i t

choose a(et) = O.

If it

is possible to be reelected, then the candidate may choose a(et) so the reelection constraint

is

just

satisfied:

would he be w i l l i n g to choose any a(et)

a(e) = Kt/e t .

In no event

larger than the smallest amount

that w i l l ensure his r e e l e c t i o n . In the remainder of t h i s section, we present a characterization of equilibrium voter and incumbent strategies Then,

we examine

electoral

control

alternative

party

(Proposition

present a comparative s t a t i c

4).

result

(Propositions

systems Finally, that

from in

implies

the

i through 3). standpoint

Proposition that

control

5,

of we

of

in-

observes the value et

and

cumbents is greater f o r more valuable o f f i c e s . After

each e l e c t i o n ,

the o f f i c e h o l d e r

15

chooses a(et) = Kt/e t i f and only i f w

(KtJ0 t) +

w+

(i)

I

and,n i f (i) is not s a t i s f i e d , he chooses a(et) = O.

In ( i ) ,

VIt+l

and

V~+I stand for the expected values of staying in office or leaving o f f i c e , respectively, given optimal play by voters and candidates from the next election forward, and a represents the (common) discount factor employed by all agents.

I t is important to note that

are independent of et and Kt .

V~+ I-_

and V~+ I_

Re-arranging terms permits us to es-

tablish the following characterization of optimal incumbent strategies: PROPOSITION 1: Given the retrospective voting rule optimal incumbent strategy is a(et) = Kt/e t i f f

I

8t ~ Kt/~-l(~(Vt+ I

_

V0 t +l ) ).

{Kt}#=O, the

(2)

PROOF: (1) implies that a(et) = Kt/8 t i f and only i f et ~ e~, I 1 - Vt+l) 0 The Inequality then where 0~ satisfies a(Vt+ = ¢(Kt/e~) . " follows from the fact that ~ is positive monotone, convex, and ¢(0) = O. In other words, the incumbent w i l l

expend effort only i f he ob-

serves a s u f f i c i e n t l y favorable value of et .

Notice that this ex-

pression implies that i f the value of office is r e l a t i v e l y small, the incumbent may choose to accept defeat though he could have been reelected. G i v e n the retrospective voting rule,

the incumbent's

optimal strategies are optimal at each time t forward.

Thus an optimal

REMARK:

strategy is credible because the incumbent would actually carry i t out for each value of et that he could realize. Or, to put i t another way, they are equilibrium strategies in each subgame (e.g.,. subgame perfect). In order to characterize an equilibrium, we must determine the optimal retrospective rule. expressed as follows:

The expected u t i l i t y

of the voter may be

oo

U = Z atKtPr{e t _ I > Kt/¢-l(a ( Vt+l - V~+l))} t=O

(3)

We can give a characterization of optimal retrospective rules by maxi-

16

mizing (3) over all retrospective rules. PROPOSITION 2:

If the et are independent, identically distributed

random variables with cumulative distribution function F(-) and density f(.),

an optimal retrospective

voting

rule

satisfies

the following

equality: Kt PROOF:

[1 - F(e~ )] f(e~) #-i(~ ( VIt + l - V0 t+l)) This follows

directly

(4)

from the first-order

conditions

derived from equation (3). The important thing to notice about equation (4) is that Kt depends I 0 Vt+l-Vt+ 1. The larger is the value of remaining in

positively on

office to the incumbent, the more the voter can ask of him.

In the

special case in which F is uniform and ¢ is the identity function, we obtain a clearer characterization. COROLLARY: If the et are independent, uniform, random variables on [ 0 , i ] , and i f ¢(a) = a and a ~ [ 0 , I ] , an optimal retrospective rule must satisfy the Following equation:

(4')

Kt = min{1/2,6(V~+I - V0+1)/2} for all t.

Equations (4) and (4') period,

the elector

can be interpreted as follows.

In each

sets Kt to equate the expected value to the i n -

cumbent of staying in o f f i c e

to the value of choosing a(et)

= 0 and

accepting defeat. PROPOSITION 3: then

e~

If

[l-F(x)]/f(x)

is monotone decreasing f u n c t i o n ,

is independent of 6, t , and W.

PROOF:

Substitute

for

Kt

using equation (4)

in the following

expression e~ : Kt/¢-l(a(VI-vO)) yields the equation

e~ : [1 - F(e~)]If(e~),

(5) which has a unique so-

lution under the assumption of monotonicity. REMARK: An optimal retrospective voting rule is subgame perfect in the sense that its restriction to any subgame is an equilibrium strategy in that subgame. Assuming he is restricted to employing some retro-

17

spective voting rule, the elector can do no better than employing a rule that satisfies

(4).

For this reason, incumbents will

regard optimal

retrospective rules as credible. COROLLARY: to l i e in [ 0 , i ] , REMARK:

I f F is uniform on [ 0 , 1 ] , then

e~ = 1/2

and

~(a) = a and a is r e s t r i c t e d

Pr({e t ~ e~}) = i / 2 .

I t f o l l o w s from the f o r m u l a t i o n t h a t any s o l u t i o n to (3)

must be s t a t i o n a r y in the sense t h a t

Kt = K f o r a l l

t.

To see t h i s ,

note t h a t i f equation (3) i s r e w r i t t e n as f o l l o w s ,

(3')

U0 = KoPr(e0 z e~) + ~U1

U1 = U0 since s t r a t e g i e s and payoffs are the same at time i as at time O.

Moreover, UI does not depend on KO.

Thus, i f K0 maximizes ( 3 ' ) ,

K0

must maximize UI, too, and so on f o r each t . In

the

stationarity pected u t i l i t y

special implies

case

of

uniformly

the f o l l o w i n g

distributed

convenient

disturbances,

expression f o r

the

ex-

of the v o t e r , using an optimal r e t r o s p e c t i v e v o t i n g r u l e ,

K:

(3")

U : K/2(1-a) = min{I/2,6(V I - V0)/2}/2(i-6).

Thus, up to the point where the expected marginal value to the incumbent of continuing

in office

exceeds 1/2,

u t i l i t y depends on this marginal value.

the voter's expected

The more attractive the present

value of office is to the incumbent, the more satisfaction the voter can anticipate. offices. receive

However, this effect holds only~or r e l a t i v e l y unattractive

Indeed, for very unattractive offices, the voter can expect to almost nothing

from the

officeholder.

For more valuable

offices, the effects of increasing value do not accrue to the elector in increased control

of the

incumbent but flow,

instead,

to the p o l i -

ticians. Having described

optimal

strategies,

we may now calculate

the

equilibrium payoffs to the game. Turning f i r s t to the incumbent we see that i f the voter is playing a stationary retrospective voting strategy with criterion K, we may write the expected value of being an incumbent, before observing e, as follows:

18

vl

m = : [W - ~( K / e ) e*

e* + : [W + avO]dF(e) 0

+ ~VI]dF(e)

The discounted expected u t i l i t y

(6)

of a candidate out of office may be

s i m i l a r l y written.

o* V0 = : [x~V I + ( I - x ) s v O ] d F ( o ) 0

m

+ : ~vOdF(o) o*

(7)

where x is the probability of obtaining office i f the current incumbent is

defeated at the next election, which is taken to be exogenously

determined.

In this interpretation a pure two-party system corresponds

to x = i ,

so that V0 = a(VI+vO)/2.

At the other extreme, a "pure"

multicandidate system would have x = O, and therefore, V0 = O. Solving (6) and (7) we obtain the following expressions for VI and V0, m [W - : e . ~ ( K x / e ) d F ( e ) ] [ 1

I Vx =

[1-a(1-xp)][1-a(1-p)]

- ~(1-xp)]

(8)

- xa2p 2

m

x~p[W -

0 =

Vx

fe,¢(Kxlo)dF(o)]

[l-~(l-xp)I[l-a(l-p)l

(9)

- xa2p 2 '

where p = F(e*) and where the subscripts indicate the dependence on x. We can now state our major results. An increase in x lowers the u t i l i t y of the voter. I - Vx 0 with respect By i m p l i c i t l y differentiating Vx = Vx

PROPOSITION 4:

PROOF:

to x and rearranging terms, we see that

aVx/Bx is negative and, from

equation (4), this implies that the derivatives of Kx and Ux with respect to x must be negative as well. REMARK:

As the number of parties is restricted, the welfare of the

elector declines. parties f a l l s

As the proof suggests, this occurs as the number of

(i.e.,

as x gets larger) and the incumbent's r e l a t i v e

valuation of office declines.

He becomes less concerned with losing

office and is, therefore, less controllable by the voter. An alternative interpretation of this result may be given i f we l e t : 0 depict the incentives of candidates rather than parties.

In this

case we see that the voters can attain higher levels of control

by

19

holding candidates rather than parties responsible for poor outcomes. This is accomplished by refusing ever to reelect an officeholder who governed in a period of poor performance. Finally,

essentially

the

same argument as

above yields

the

following result: PROPOSITION 5: PROOF: solving f o r

The u t i l i t y of the voter is increasing in W.

By implicitly differentiating ~V~/~W,

V~ with respect to W and

we see that Vx is increasing in W.

This implies

that U increases in W, too. Most of the conclusions that are drawn from t h i s simple model of repeated elections are in accord with i n t u i t i o n . that

voters

office

is

discounted. office,

have more control relatively

high

over officeholders

and

when the

Like Barro, we find when the

future

is

less

value of heavily

To the extent that voters can d i r e c t l y a f f e c t the value of

they should choose i t

optimally.

How t h i s should be done is

discussed in Barro's paper, and we r e f e r the reader to his discussion. Roughly speaking, an increase in the value of o f f i c e can be expected not only to cost something but also to increase the level of competition f o r o f f i c e among nonincumbents ( t h i s is not e x p l i c i t l y modelled e i t h e r here or in Barro's paper). termined by the

To the extent that the value of o f f i c e is de-

(legal or i l l e g a l )

behavior of incumbent p o l i t i c i a n s ,

that value may tend to be set at a higher level than the voters would wish.

In e i t h e r case, however, we might expect systems to evolve in

such a way that p o l i t i c i a n s desire to hold onto t h e i r o f f i c e s and in which, therefore, the electorate is accorded a modicum of c o n t r o l . Perhaps more surprising merits of

party systems.

is our conclusion about the comparative

While our depiction of the two systems is

s i m p l i s t i c , we believe that the basic conclusion w i l l

hold up in more

sophisticated models of repeated elections as long as there is no motive f o r the development of party reputations.

As long as the p a r t i e s do not

d i f f e r in t h e i r c a p a b i l i t i e s or preferences in some unobserved way, they have no way of d i s t i n g u i s h i n g themselves in the minds of the voters.

In

such a s e t t i n g , the r e s t r i c t i o n of e l e c t o r a l competition to two p a r t i e s has the e f f e c t of decreasing the level of voter control holders.

over o f f i c e -

Voters are better o f f in t h i s model to the extent that they

can prevent the system from evolving into two-party competition.

In a

two-party system the loss of o f f i c e is not as consequential as i t would

20

be in a pure candidate (or, indeed, a multiparty) system and so officeholders are not given a strong incentive to pay attention to the interests of the electors.

4.

ELECTORALCONTROLWITH A NONHOMOGENEOUSELECTORATE

The development of assumption formance.

of

the model of electoral

homogeneous voter

control

preferences

While there is some empirical

was based on the

over

government

evidence in favor of the hy-

pothesis that voter evaluations of incumbents are correlated, still

reason to suspect that

government performance.

there is

voters may disagree in t h e i r ratings

Indeed, many of the real

parties and candidates may be due to d i s t r i b u t i o n a l p o l i c i e s they pursue.

per-

differences

of

among

differences in the

How far may the results of our model be extended

in a world in which the voters maintain separate evaluative standards f o r officeholders? We begin by considering Section 2 and extending i t only about the quantity,

a simple s p e c i a l i z a t i o n

of the model in

to the case of N voters, each of whom cares xi

that

he receives.

We l e t

the value of

o f f i c e be W, and the incumbent's objective is to maximize W - a; but, in this

case,

the incumbent must also decide how to divide the output,

Ba(6), among the voters.

Thus, his strategies are represented by an

(N+l)-vector (a,x), where x=(xl,x2,x 3 . . . . . XN) and where Zxi = ea(e). The game proceeds just as before: Ki ,

the voters announce t h e i r retro-

spective voting

levels,

and then the incumbent observes Bt

and

chooses (a,x).

Then each voter observes the output he receives and

votes to re-elect the incumbent i f and only i f i t is satisfactory in the sense that x i ~ Ki .

For the present, we r e s t r i c t our attention to

stationary equilibria in order to economize on notation.

This will not

entail any essential loss of generality. The following

proposition

characterizes the equilibria

of

this

model: PROPOSITION 6:

I f is an equilibrium, i t is

equal to zero in all i t s components. PROOF: Given the voters' choice of Ki , i = 1,...,N, the incumbent w i l l choose the majority coalition, ~, to minimize Zxi c

subject to the

21

constraint that x i ~ Ki for all i ~ ~.

Obviously, this implies that x i

= Ki for i ~ ~ and that ~ is a minimal majority.

I f this minimum is

positive, any j i c would have been better off to offer Kj