Political Legitimacy in the Real Normative World: The ...

6 downloads 0 Views 189KB Size Report
3 See, for example, Galston 2010, 385–411; Geuss 2008; Honig 1993; Philp 2007; ... 'Political realism', as Bernard Williams has preferred to call it, is indeed far ...
B.J.Pol.S. 00, 1–19 Copyright r Cambridge University Press, 2013 doi:10.1017/S0007123413000148

Political Legitimacy in the Real Normative World: The Priority of Morality and the Autonomy of the Political Q1

EVA ERMAN

AND

NIKLAS MO¨ LLER*

1 2 3 4

According to what has recently been labeled ‘political realism’ in political theory, ‘political moralists’ such as Rawls and Dworkin misconstrue the political domain by presuming that morality has priority over politics, thus overlooking that the political is an autonomous domain with its own distinctive conditions and normative sources. Political realists argue that this presumption, commonly referred to as the ‘ethics first premise’, has to be abandoned in order to properly theorize a normative conception of political legitimacy. This article critically examines two features of political realism, which so far have received too little systematic philosophical analysis: the political realist critique of political moralism and the challenges facing political realism in its attempt to offer an alternative account of political legitimacy. Two theses are defended. First, to the extent that proponents of political realism wish to hold onto a normative conception of political legitimacy, refuting wholesale the ethics first premise leads to a deadlock, since it throws the baby out with the bathwater by closing the normative space upon which their account of political legitimacy relies. This is called the ‘necessity thesis’: all coherent and plausible conceptions of political legitimacy must hold onto the ethics first premise. Secondly, accepting this premise – and thus defending an ethics first view – does not entail that the political domain must be seen as a subordinate arena for the application of moral principles, that political normativity is reduced to morality or that morality trumps other reasons in political decision making, as claimed by political realists. Rather, the ethics first view is compatible with an autonomous political domain that makes room for an account of political legitimacy that is defined by and substantiated from sources of normativity specifically within the political. This is called the ‘compatibility thesis’.

5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24

An intensified discussion about the role of normative ideals has re-emerged in the debate on justice in political philosophy. What often falls under the heading of ‘ideal theory’, represented by liberal egalitarians such as John Rawls and Ronald Dworkin, is under attack from those who stress that any plausible theory of justice must take much more seriously the non-ideal circumstances consisting of the relations of domination and power under which principles of justice are supposed to be formulated, justified and applied. Above all, the criticism from the ‘non-ideal theory’ standpoint has highlighted problems pertaining to action-guidance, practical import and feasibility,1 which have in turn been

25

* Department of Government, Uppsala University (email: [email protected]) and Department of Philosophy, Royal Institute of Technology (email: [email protected]). We owe special thanks to Richard North, Thomas Christiano, Terry Macdonald, Bob Goodin, Andrew Williams, Laura Valentini, Rainer Forst, John Cantwell and Christine Chwaszcza for comments on earlier drafts of this article. Thanks also to the journal’s editors and anonymous reviewers. In addition, Eva Erman wishes to thank the participants at the Authority of Global Institutions workshop in Barcelona (June 2012), and Samantha Besson, Jose´ Luis Martı´ and Andrew Williams for inviting me; as well as the participants at the How Can International Political Theory Get ‘‘Real’’? workshop in Melbourne (March 2012) and the Critical Theory Roundtable in Prague (May 2012). Moreover, she wishes to thank Riksbankens Jubileumsfond (RJ) for financing the Transdemos Programme. Niklas Mo¨ller thanks the Swedish Research Council Formas for its generous funding of this research. 1 See, for example, Farrelly 2007, 844–64; Mills 2005, 165–84; Sen 2009.

26 27 28 29 30 31 32

2 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67 68 69

E R M A N A N D M O¨ L L E R

met with several responses in defence of ideal theory.2 A similar criticism against ideal theory has emerged as an approach broadly labeled ‘political realism’ in political and democratic theory. However, while the latter criticism has been discussed as part of the debate on justice, political realists make some distinct charges and suggestions that have thus far largely escaped systematic scrutiny. These charges are directed at the ‘political moralism’ (or ‘liberal idealism’) of Rawls’ and Dworkin’s liberal theories, which allegedly regard the political domain as subordinate to the moral domain, and mainly an arena for the application of moral principles. By adopting such an ‘ethics first’ premise – that is, a premise that gives priority to morality over politics – political moralism overlooks that the political is an autonomous domain with its own distinctive conditions, normative sources and standards.3 Political realists argue that in order for normative political theory to be able to offer a coherent, plausible and convincing conception of political legitimacy, the ethics first premise must be rejected. This article critically examines two features of political realism that have thus far received too little systematic philosophical analysis: the political realist critique of political moralism and the challenges facing political realism in its attempt to offer a normative account of political legitimacy.4 Two theses are defended. First, to the extent that proponents of political realism wish to hold onto a normative conception of political legitimacy, refuting the ethics first premise wholesale leads to a deadlock, since it throws the baby out with the bathwater by closing the normative space upon which their account of political legitimacy relies. We call this the ‘necessity thesis’, which states that all coherent and plausible conceptions of political legitimacy must hold onto the ethics first premise. Secondly, accepting this premise – and thus defending an ethics first view – does not entail that the political domain must be seen as a subordinate arena for the application of moral principles, that political normativity is reduced to morality or that morality trumps other reasons in political decision making, as claimed by political realists. Rather, the ethics first view is compatible with an autonomous political domain that makes room for an account of political legitimacy that is defined by and substantiated from sources of normativity specifically within the political. We call this the ‘compatibility thesis’. The structure of the argument is straightforward. We start off with a brief sketch of the realist critique of political moralism, in particular the problem pertaining to the ethics first premise, and present the political realists’ alternative approach to political legitimacy. Secondly, we defend the necessity thesis in three steps: showing that political realists are ambivalent in their conceptualization of legitimacy; that they misconstrue the relationship between morality and politics; and that their own ‘legitimacy from within the political’ stance is also ultimately anchored to the ethics first premise, as are all defensible 2

See, for example, Erman and Mo¨ller 2013, 19–44; Estlund 2008; Estlund 2011, 207–37; Simmons 2010, 5–36; Valentini 2009, 332–55. 3 See, for example, Galston 2010, 385–411; Geuss 2008; Honig 1993; Philp 2007; Philp 2010, 466–84; Stears 2007, 505–31; Williams 2005. Note that while Williams uses the term ‘ethics first view’ synonymously with ‘political moralism’, we restrict the former term for views that accept the ethics first premise. Cf. Geuss 2008. 4 For a recent exception, see Philp 2012, which argues that political realists ought to acknowledge a much more complex and subtle relationship between morality and politics. However, rather than undertaking a systematic philosophical analysis of political realism and its critique of political moralism, Philp primarily offers a careful analysis of the nature of evaluative judgement in the study of politics, stressing the pluralist character of political theory.

Political Legitimacy in the Real Normative World

3

conceptions of political legitimacy. The third section is devoted to defending the compatibility thesis and thus the view that the ethics first premise is compatible with holding onto an autonomous political domain. We show that the way political realists theorize the notion of the autonomy of the political, it is either unreasonably demanding (what we call ‘hyperautonomy of the political’) or thin enough to be consistent with the ethics first premise of any political moralist (what we call ‘basic autonomy of the political’). We conclude that while any reasonable conception of political legitimacy is consistent with the latter, there is room for developing and justifying a thicker notion of autonomy from sources of normativity specifically within the political, as political realists wish to do.

70

POLITICAL LEGITIMACY: FROM POLITICAL MORALISM TO POLITICAL REALISM

80

Before we begin our analysis of moralist and realist accounts of political legitimacy, we should first say a few words about what political legitimacy is. It is commonly described as a virtue of political arrangements or institutions and the decisions (policies, laws) made within them. In political theory, it refers to the justification of coercive power or the justification and sanctioning of political authority, where authority usually signifies the right to rule and in most cases entails political obligations. While there may be disagreements between individual theorists in this debate concerning how best to characterize this concept in detail, there is wide agreement on this general understanding of the term. Realists disagree about what legitimacy requires, that is, the proper normative criteria of legitimacy. It should also be noted that a distinction is sometimes made in empirical studies of political legitimacy between ‘legitimation’ as a process (with the aim of generating legitimacy) and ‘legitimacy’ as an outcome (or state of affairs). However this distinction is not used in this debate. The criteria of political legitimacy that are defended by moralists and realists alike may be procedural or substantive (or both).

81

Problems of Political Moralism

95

‘Political realism’, as Bernard Williams has preferred to call it, is indeed far from a unified political theory. It consists of a rich and pluralist group of political theorists from diverging quarters. Still, they share enough features to represent a relatively clear dissenting position to the liberal idealist theory represented by, for example, Rawls and Dworkin. They also share enough assumptions to represent an alternative approach to political legitimacy.5 In brief, political realists unite in two general points of criticisms. The first involves problems of action-guidance and feasibility. In line with non-ideal theorists in the debate on justice, they doubt whether the utopianism of political moralism has any practical import and whether it is of any relevance for political theory. The second criticism concerns conceptual and normative questions pertaining to political legitimacy. These points are certainly deeply connected for political realists, since a defensible theory of political legitimacy (in their view) would have to be feasible and take seriously the empirical conditions under which politics is pursued. However, this article focuses on the second point and hence on what political realists have to offer in terms of a normative theory of political legitimacy (we will say more about this restriction below). It will only bring up criticism related to the first point in cases in which it is relevant to do so.

96

5

For an overview, see Galston 2010.

71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79

82 83 84 85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94

97 98 99 100 101 102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 111

4 112 113 114 115 116 117 118 119 120 121 122 123 124 125 126 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135 136 137 138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146

E R M A N A N D M O¨ L L E R

The core of the second critique is the charge that political moralism cannot offer a coherent and plausible theory of political legitimacy because it does not regard the political as an autonomous domain, but rather as an arena for the application of moral principles. Since it is anchored to an ethics first premise, which prioritizes morality over politics, it is argued that political moralism ‘reduces political normativity to morality’6 and represents a ‘desire to evade, displace, or escape from politics’.7 According to realists, this ethics first premise has several unfortunate implications for how political legitimacy is conceptualized. First, political legitimacy is seen as a pre-political concept in the sense that it assumes that significant consensus must be in place ‘before politics as an activity can, properly speaking, begin’.8 In other words, pre-political abstract moral principles are allegedly applied to the practice of politics.9 In Williams’ view, political moralists assume the moral to be prior and external to the political, either expressed in terms of an ‘enactment model’ – according to which political institutions and actions are intended to express moral principles, ideals and values (the prime example being utilitarianism); or a ‘structural model’, according to which such principles offer external constraints on what politics can rightfully do (the prime example being Rawls’ theory of justice).10 In both models, political theory starts ‘from outside politics, whereby the demands of morality give content to the principles of cooperation or legitimate political action’.11 Realists argue that political legitimacy on a political moralist account is flawed because it does not take into consideration that consensus cannot be achieved through a philosophical argument that builds moral premises into a stylized choice situation.12 As an ‘artifact’ of politics, consensus cannot exist before the political and thus be a precondition of politics. Rather, it is only by employing political power that general agreement of any sort is possible and achievable. Rejecting the ethics first premise, political realists argue that the normative sources of political legitimacy must be sought solely within politics rather than from an external moral standpoint.13 Above all, since politics is inherently an exercise of collective decision making, realists cast doubt on the assumption that individual moral norms carry over to collective political action.14 Not only do public decisions differ from private ones in numerous respects; politics is most of the time a dirty business in which ‘we desire principled politicians but expect – even oblige – them to commit unprincipled acts’.15 A second implication of the ethics first premise, realists argue, is that it leads to depoliticization, that is, to a view of the political domain as deprived of any real politics and unable to offer any ‘remotely plausible account of political agency’.16 In Raymond Geuss’ words, ‘ethics is dead politics’.17 By regarding political legitimacy as a pre-political

6

Newey 2010, 449. Galston 2010, 386. 8 Sleat 2010, 490–1. 9 Rossi 2012, 149–64. 10 Williams 2005, 1–2. Similarly, Rossi (2012, 151) claims that political moralists see morality as ‘external and prior to politics’. 11 Sleat 2010, 486 (emphasis added); see also Geuss 2008. 12 Galston 2010, 387. 13 Bellamy 2010, 412–30; Mouffe 2005; Sleat 2010; Williams 2005. 14 Newey 2010, 450. 15 Bellamy 2010, 414. 16 Horton 2010, 437. 17 Geuss 2008, 42. 7

Political Legitimacy in the Real Normative World

5

concept, liberal idealists attempt to depoliticize and sanitize real-world politics from the outside by eliminating ‘political sleights of hand from collective decision-making’.18 But this cannot be right, realists complain. Since politics concerns public reasons, there cannot be any general way in which to construct political agency from individual reasons for action.19

147

A Political Realist Account of Political Legitimacy

151

Against the backdrop of these criticisms, realists recommend shifting the agenda of political theory away from debating minor revisions of Rawls’ difference principle towards focusing on the contexts and processes through which a citizenry addresses shared problems.20 To begin with, Williams stresses, the fact that realists aim to elaborate political legitimacy from normative sources in the political domain does not imply that politics is amoral or immoral. It simply means that the appropriate standards of evaluation arise from within the political rather than from an external moral standpoint.21 While no direct appeal is made to ‘moral norms of a pre-political nature’, a ‘code of political ethics’ might still exist.22 Moreover, instead of focusing on consensus, political realists start from a notion of disagreement and commonly see ineliminable conflict as the essence of politics. From this standpoint, politics is foremost and unavoidably about trying to achieve some sort of social order. According to Williams, legitimacy is a matter of responding to the ‘first’ political question, which is concerned with securing order and preventing chaos. Peace, stability and security must be ensured first, since they serve as a pre-condition for any other political objectives, such as justice or fairness.23 While this does not require political realists to presume that people must necessarily see peace and security as supreme and overriding goods, they are fundamental goods for politics since they are an essential condition for achieving almost any other goods.24 In other words, a basic level of social order must be maintained that is at least sufficient to enable persons to live minimally worthwhile lives and secure the conditions of co-operation.25 That said, following Williams’ axiom ‘might is not right’, not all social orders that achieve this can be considered legitimate. For example, ‘a peaceful situation preserved entirely through suppression or tyranny, or at the extreme by the exclusion or even elimination of those who do not accept it’, is not legitimate.26 To distinguish legitimate from non-legitimate power, realists commonly anchor political legitimacy in two conditions, which we here call ‘the agreement condition’ and ‘the autonomy condition’. Concerning the agreement condition, Horton claims that for an arrangement to be legitimate it has to be ‘broadly ‘‘acceptable’’ or ‘‘agreeable’’ to those who are party to it’.27 As long as such acceptance ‘is not the product of clear, willful, systematic and comprehensive deception by those with political power, the reasons why it is accepted can

152

18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27

Bellamy 2010, 415. Bellamy 2010; Newey 2010; Philp 2010. Galston 2010, 394. Williams 2005, 77; Sleat 2010. Bellamy 2010, 416. Williams 2005, 3. Horton 2010, 438. Horton 2010, 438; Williams 2005, 3. Horton 2010, 439. Horton 2010.

148 149 150

153 154 155 156 157 158 159 160 161 162 163 164 165 166 167 168 169 170 171 172 173 174 175 176 177 178 179 180 181 182

6

E R M A N A N D M O¨ L L E R

202

be many and various’.28 Similarly, Newey argues that political legitimacy requires an agreement that is ‘thought of as free’. However, he accepts that political reasons, such as reasons for agreement, are often artifacts of the political process.29 Bellamy also argues that legitimacy requires ‘some degree of willing consent on the part of the ruled’.30 The autonomy condition is to be understood in a weak sense, defining the subjects who are supposed to reach this agreement (or perceive it as such) and express some form of ‘self-determination’ or ‘self-authorization’ on behalf of those who are involved in, or are part of, the social order in question. Being part of the social order is defined in terms of subjectedness, such that the parties ‘subject to’ the social order or political authority are those who are supposed to agree to it31 or be offered justification in terms of sufficient reasons for accepting it.32 In Horton’s view, for example, a political order meets the conditions of legitimacy if it is ‘broadly acceptable to those subject to it’.33 In addition to these shared features, Williams adds further components that seem to make his realist account more universalist. While he stresses that any response to the first question of politics is a temporary solution, the paradigmatic rejection of slavery has universal applicability since the mere circumstance of some subjects being de facto ruled by others is ‘no legitimation of their being radically disadvantaged’.34 In Williams’ view, it is deductively true from the axiom ‘might is not right’ that some justifications of power are simply a violation of universal (human) rights, the latter of which can be derived from the ‘universal materials of politics’.35

203

THE NECESSITY THESIS: THE PRIORITY OF MORALITY

204

The Normative Wiggle Room of Political Realism

205

As mentioned above, our analysis is directed at the normative aspect of realism, and leaves the extensively debated questions of feasibility and action-guidance aside. We do not deny that feasibility is a central aspect of realist accounts of political legitimacy. Indeed it is. However, although feasibility sets constraints on the normative demands of a society, this article analyzes the normative claims made by realists within these limits, whatever they are. As we have seen, instead of relying on prior moral and idealized assumptions, realist legitimacy responds to the historical context of a political arrangement or polity.36 At the same time, it relies on normative conditions, mainly on what we call the agreement

183 184 185 186 187 188 189 190 191 192 193 194 195 196 197 198 199 200 201

206 207 208 209 210 211 212 213

28

It seems likely that Horton has actual agreement in mind here, even if he at several places expresses the agreement condition as some kind of hypothetical consent in terms of ’acceptability’. 29 Newey 2010, 460. 30 Bellamy 2010, 424. 31 Bellamy 2010, 424; Horton 2010, 439–40; Newey 2010, 460–1. For Newey, the source of normativity in terms of free agreement follows from the conditions of collective action in the sense that it is necessary for a person to regard her will as her own in order to incorporate it in a collective will. Only in this way, argues Newey, can she regard herself as autonomous and self-determining in relation to it – that is, as an author of her actions (Newey 2010). 32 Williams 2005, 6. 33 Horton 2010, 440. 34 Williams 2005, 5. 35 Williams 2005, 6, 59. Indeed, the ontological and normative status of Williams’ universal rights are rather unclear. He probably would have diverged from other political realists had he further developed his political theory in relation to his internalism in ethics; see Bavister-Gould 2011. 36 Galston 2010, 387; Philp 2010, 466; Sleat 2010, 496.

Political Legitimacy in the Real Normative World

7

condition and the autonomy condition, which are meant to ensure that not all forms of agreements count as legitimate. In order for a political order to be legitimate, the agreement (Horton) or willing consent (Bellamy) must be perceived as free (Newey), and thus cannot rely on means that are too tyrannical (Horton), be coerced (Williams) or be a result of total deception (Horton). The question is, in light of the realist emphasis on the actual circumstances of politics, how are these normative restrictions established? Basically, either the two conditions of legitimacy are established by actual political processes, or they are not. If they are indeed established by actual processes, such that a political order is legitimate insofar as it is in accordance with the process in question, we have started on a regress of justification. Because what if this process is due to a too tyrannical order? If all we do is adhere to a new actual (meta) process or arrangement, we are merely pushing the justificatory question one more step, not responding to it. Consequently, realists are well aware that the only way of out this regress is to acknowledge that not all sources of legitimacy are due to the actual political context in which they are formulated. Legitimacy in this sense transcends actual politics, as it were.37 There is a sense, of course, in which all normative principles that have ever been formulated are due to actual processes, namely in the sense that they all, as a matter of physical necessity, have been formed through an historical process. Thus there is no other way than within actual politics (in the broadest sense of the term) to formulate, question and argue for what the justificatory sources of legitimacy are. But this must be kept separate from the claim, rejected by realists, that actual processes decide the conditions of legitimacy. As history has taught us, actual processes come in all flavors. They have resulted not only in the values that realists endorse but also, for example, that ‘might is right’, the idea that some people are worth more than others, that birth constitutes a legitimate ground for ruling and so on. Paying close attention to context, in particular to the limits set by how politics works, realists consider the (historically formulated) available norms. Moreover, similar to any other normative account of political legitimacy, they pick out some and reject others when formulating and justifying their notion of legitimacy. It is only in this way that realists become equipped to say that some actual rule making, or some actual authority, is simply not legitimate (for example, by being too tyrannical). In this sense, the realist notion of legitimacy transcends actual politics. One possible objection to this line of reasoning would be that political realists are supposed to be interpreted as putting forward a relativist position such that legitimacy stems from the convictions of the public and nothing else. However even if such relativist claims are made, such as when Bellamy says that ‘[u]ltimately, the source of public reasons is the public themselves’,38 this interpretation is not overall plausible in view of the commitment made by the same theorist (and by political realists generally) to the restrictions on how such beliefs may be caused in order to constitute legitimacy. The prohibition of agreement by coercion, deception and tyranny is de facto an endorsement of sources of normativity that transcend actual politics. From this we infer that political realism generally is to be interpreted as a normative project that, as Philp says, ‘provides the basis for a contextualist but non-relativist account of ‘‘what is to be done’’’.39 37

Note here that we use ‘transcends’ in the commonsensical meaning of going beyond something (in this case, the present political context), which should not be conflated with the technical and more metaphysically laden (typically Kantian) notion often referred to as a ‘transcendental argument’, used against skeptics to prove the existence of, for example, the external world or other minds. 38 Bellamy 2010, 416. 39 Philp 2010, 466.

214 215 216 217 218 219 220 221 222 223 224 225 226 227 228 229 230 231 232 233 234 235 236 237 238 239 240 241 242 243 244 245 246 247 248 249 250 251 252 253 254

8 255 256 257 258 259 260 261 262 263 264 265 266 267 268 269 270 271 272 273 274 275 276 277 278 279 280 281 282 283 284 285 286 287 288

E R M A N A N D M O¨ L L E R

Another objection might be that the normative restrictions on legitimate agreement on the realist account are supposed to be understood as being grounded merely in the empirical conditions of the political community as such – that is, in terms of conditions that must be fulfilled in order for the community to persist. On some realist conceptions, such as Williams’, it is clear from the start that legitimacy is more than this: ‘the power of coercion offered simply as the power of coercion cannot justify its own use’.40 In a similar vein, Galston argues that the realist emphasis on context does not imply ‘that the concept of universal principles makes no sense; basic human rights exist and apply to all’.41 On other conceptions, however, there seems to be a certain ambivalence concerning the status of the normativity. Horton, for example, claims that ‘political theory can only tell it as it is, mapping rather than seeking to adjudicate rival perspectives’.42 But since his theory relies on a notion of agreement that shares with other realists similar normative restrictions on what is acceptable for legitimacy – such that it has to be broadly ‘acceptable’ or ‘agreeable’ to those who are party to it43 – he cannot avoid the transcendent normativity that he seems reluctant to embrace. Surely, there are other possible arrangements if we were merely interested in the persistence conditions of a political community. We infer that the realist conception of legitimacy is best interpreted as resting on a source of normativity that is dependent on, but still transcends, the political processes. While realists stress the contextual factors of real politics, such that ‘reasons for acting politicallyy are largely artefacts of the political culture’,44 they still endorse that not all reasons are so constituted.45 Thus they adhere to values or principles that have priority to and transcend the actual political process, in order to distinguish between (1) fulfilled empirical conditions for, say, peace and security to live worthwhile lives (not legitimate) and (2) empirical conditions for peace and security to live worthwhile lives that are fulfilled in an accepted way (legitimate). Indeed, this is in accordance with what is commonly seen as a truism about normativity in the philosophical literature, namely, that it is always in principle possible for a person, group or community to be wrong about what should be done.46 Regardless of how empirically informed we are, and how contextual a criterion of legitimacy may be, a realist account that equates normative criteria of legitimacy with people’s beliefs about what is legitimate shoulders a heavy justificatory burden.47 We next turn to the second question about the source of normativity, viz. how these realist transcendental (grounding) values should be characterized in order to analyze how the relationship between the moral and political domains is construed by political realists. 40

Williams 2005, 5. Galston 2010, 396. 42 Horton 2010, 443. 43 Horton 2010, 439. 44 Newey 2010, 449. 45 In Newey’s case, this is even an endorsement of idealized aspects of acceptance, albeit arguably in a weaker form than suggested by political moralists. 46 This is why it is important, even for an account that relies heavily on normative assessment as the grounding feature of conceptual content, to ‘institute objective norms, according to which the correctness of an application of a concept answers to the facts about the object to which it is applied, in such a way that anyone (indeed everyone) in the linguistic community may be wrong about it’ (Brandom 1994, xvii). 47 Now, the skeptic may object that a theorist’s account of legitimacy is equally a belief about what is legitimate. This is probably true. Strictly speaking, an account of legitimacy is a theory, presumably a set of propositions. Hopefully, these propositions correspond at least to the beliefs of the theorist. That said, she would presumably not claim that her holding those beliefs is what justifies the account. 41

Political Legitimacy in the Real Normative World

9

Flawed Conceptions of the Ethics First Premise

289

Does the fact that political realists’ values transcend actual politics entail that realists must also subscribe to the ethics first premise? Thomas Hurka, in his review of Geuss’ Philosophy and Real Politics, believes so.48 In what bears structural similarities to our argument above, he reasons that when justifying every situation-dependent value, there is another value that justifies this value; we eventually reach a value that is not contextual but holds universally, which means to ‘revert to the ethics-first view’.49 These structural similarities notwithstanding, Hurka puts forward a different, much more controversial argument. Even if we accept this argument, his conclusion about an ethics first view does not follow. Our claim in the previous subsection was that the realist conception of legitimacy fundamentally rests on values that transcend the actual processes of the political arena. But we have not yet said anything about the form that these values must take. Hurka makes the stronger claim that they have to be in the form of universal principles, and concludes from this that realists must accept an ethics first view. But this is a question-begging argument, since it starts out by assuming that realists (or at least Geuss) deny that there are any generally true principles and goes on to state that underneath every contextual principle there has to be a general one. In the present context, there is an even more crucial problem with Hurka’s argument: it simply assumes that any universal value or principle is moral. As we saw in the previous subsection, political realists typically do not deny grounding principles; on the contrary, they are committed to the agreement and autonomy conditions of legitimacy. So they would deny particularism for political legitimacy and instead ‘use a principle that doesn’0 t need special justification in this society because it holds universally’.50 However, they could still insist that these principles are political and not moral – but the latter is precisely what the principle-denying theoretician would resist.51 As will be shown in the next subsection, political realists do in fact rely on the ethics first premise and thus prioritize morality over politics. However, we will argue that they have misconstrued what this priority consists of. Before turning to our argumentation, we should first say a few words about the notions of the political and moral domains on the realist conception. To our knowledge, political realists have given little in the way of an unambiguous characterization of the two domains. Indeed, they sometimes even argue that we should not even try, since ‘disputes over the extension of ‘‘politics’’ are themselves irreducibly political’.52 Still, in practice they seem to rely on a typical understanding of the two domains. According to this view, the moral (or ethical)53 domain is primarily about

290

48

Hurka 2009. Hurka 2009. 50 Hurka 2009. 51 This is a living debate in moral philosophy, in which particularists argue that morality is essentially contextual, and that ‘principles’ are merely rules of thumb that do not hold generally (cf. Hooker and Little 2000). 52 Newey 2010, 459. 53 We will use the terms ‘ethics’ and ‘morality’ interchangeably. Here we deviate from some realists – for example Williams, who uses ‘morality’ to denote a system of standards and norms, whereas ‘ethics’ is used in a broader sense (see Williams 1985) – as well as some supposed moralists (for example, Rawls and Habermas), who use ‘ethics’ to refer to ideas of ‘the good’ and ‘morality’ to refer to universal principles and ideas of ‘the right’. As will be further discussed below, these more fine-grained distinctions are not important for our purposes, since our two theses do not concern the relationship between the moral and ethical but between the moral/ethical domain and the political domain. 49

291 292 293 294 295 296 297 298 299 300 301 302 303 304 305 306 307 308 309 310 311 312 313 314 315 316 317 318 319 320 321 322

10 323 324 325 326 327 328 329 330 331 332 333 334 335 336 337 338 339 340 341 342 343 344 345 346 347 348 349 350 351 352 353 354 355 356 357 358 359 360 361 362

E R M A N A N D M O¨ L L E R

how we, as individuals, ought to live our lives. Moral values and principles are those that justify our actions, beliefs and intentions, distinguishing what is right from wrong, or good from bad. Such moral values and principles may be structural, such as that of equal consideration for everyone,54 or they may be more substantial, such as W. D. Ross’ duty of non-maleficence.55 The political domain, on the other hand, concerns how we ought to live our lives on the societal level. According to realists, politics is primarily about collective action and collective decision making pertaining to governmental bodies and institutions, and consists of social relations involving power and authority.56 Typical political values and principles are collective self-determination, political equality and the principle of inclusion. Naturally, all characterizations of the moral and political domains are bound to be controversial, but since our arguments are directed at political realism, we will accept this realist reading of the two domains unless explicitly stated otherwise (see below for further discussion). Let us now turn to the ethics first premise. Political realists claim that this premise entails that morality is ‘prior’ or ‘external’ to politics. Matt Sleat provides a typical example of how the ethics first premise is conceptualized: A consequence of undertaking political theory in this moralistic manner is that it starts from outside politics, whereby the demands of morality give content to the principles of cooperation or legitimate political action, or political structures and institutions are designed according to prior moral stipulations.57

Moreover, realists often perceive such ‘prior moral stipulations’ as fixed and static, in comparison to the dynamic nature of politics. Newey, for example, argues that ‘[l]iberal political design takes morality as fixed, and politics as negotiable’.58 In contrast, legitimacy on the realist account ‘must be generated from within politics itself rather than reflect the demands of an external moral requirement’.59 To begin with, a dichotomy of morality as fixed and pre-given and politics as dynamic and negotiable does not hold, whether we refer to the practices or the content in question. Interpreted as practices of morality/politics, the several thousand-year-old debate in normative moral philosophy bears witness to the fact that morality is just as ‘negotiable’ as politics. Indeed, influential moral philosophers have long taken the moral domain to be one of ‘essentially contestable’ claims.60 However, if we interpret them as justificatory principles or claims themselves, they (as we have demonstrated above) pace the contextual factors of politics, are also essentially fixed on the realist conception of the political. In other words, in both the moral and the political domains, we justify our actions or processes with reference to principles and claims that we treat as fixed, even if the content of these fixed points is always under debate. The interpretation of morality as ‘prior to’ politics is equally hard to get off the ground. If what realists refer to here is epistemological or conceptual priority, it seems to be too strong a claim. We seem to be able to gain knowledge of – hence understand – what the political domain is without relying on prior knowledge of the moral domain. Similarly, our 54 55 56 57 58 59 60

See, for example, Rachels 1999. Ross 1930. Bellamy 2010; Newey 2010; Sleat 2010. Sleat 2010, 486. Newey 2010, 463. Sleat 2010, 487. See, for example, Wiggins 1990, 61–85.

Political Legitimacy in the Real Normative World

11

political concepts do not seem to presuppose moral ones; indeed, we seem perfectly able to understand the political domain through our understanding of collective action, the processes of actual politics and so on – aspects that are all internal to the political domain. Another interpretation of ‘prior to’ that fits with realist claims about ‘external’ to or ‘outside’ of politics is a temporal, presumably causal, relationship. But the idea that moral concerns always come first, and somehow by themselves cause political concerns, seems equally problematic. A question of whether a decision is politically legitimate would, from this perspective, start with a moral concern. But this interpretation seems just as implausible as the conceptual claim. Although there are plenty of cases in which moral concerns cause political concerns, such as when infringements on people’s ownership rights cause them to call for political action (and legislation), in many other cases political concerns are the initiating force, such as when people encounter collective action problems. Moreover, even when moral considerations cause political action, why could it not be in the very context of politics that these considerations become salient? Although this is of course controversial, the above example of infringements of the right to private property may be a morally relevant fact only due to its political context, rather than because it has any independent or prior force. A moral consideration may, it seems to us, be ‘generated from within politics itself’ and still reflect the demands of a moral requirement. There is no reason (apart from a rhetorical one) to claim that this requirement is somehow ‘external’. To conclude, the realist claim that the ethics first view would entail that the moral domain is prior or external to the political domain – either conceptually, epistemically, temporally or casually – builds on a misconstrual of the relationship between the moral and political domains. However, realists fail to address at least one notion of priority. While explanatory priority may refer to the sort of epistemological or conceptual priority that we have already dismissed, it may also be interpreted as a justificatory notion. We call this notion justificatory priority, and will argue below that morality does indeed have this priority to politics on any plausible notion of political legitimacy.

363 364 365 366 367 368 369 370 371 372 373 374 375 376 377 378 379 380 381 382 383 384 385 386 387 388 389

The Justificatory Priority of Morality

390

In order to show that political realists seem to – and must – subscribe to the ethics first premise understood as a justificatory priority, let us return to the agreement and autonomy conditions of political legitimacy. Evidently, political realists do not wish to reduce legitimacy to any social order that is stable and secure. The normative work of the agreement and autonomy conditions is meant to distinguish legitimate (acceptable) stability and security from non-legitimate (unacceptable) stability and security. However, it is not self-evident (or an inherent feature of political decision procedures and processes) that those who are subject to political authority, in the sense of being governed by it, would have to agree on it for acceptability.61 From the point of view of acceptable stability and security, there are many alternative versions of normative conditions. For example, why not instead let citizens who contribute most to stability have twice as much to say in the authorization (acceptance) of political power, and prohibit those who contribute nothing or very little from having a say as long as they benefit from this social order?

391

61

Unless, of course, we adopted Williams’ normative notion of ‘the political’, according to which an illegitimate order such as slavery is not within the political. Hence, according to his view, politics equals legitimate politics. However, this is not the way the term ‘politics’ is commonly applied in this debate.

392 393 394 395 396 397 398 399 400 401 402 403 404

12

E R M A N A N D M O¨ L L E R

439

Based on our analysis, the only plausible explanation for why realists stick to the agreement condition as a prerequisite of acceptability is that they ultimately ground political legitimacy in an egalitarian premise of some sort, for example ‘equal acceptability’. But such a premise is constituted by the moral values of freedom and equality, regardless of whether these values (and the way they are integrated into the account of political legitimacy) are part of a political morality – that is, a morality that emerges in the political domain – or are in some sense ‘before’ or ‘external’ to it.62 The same applies to the autonomy condition, which is expressed in terms of ‘equal subjectedness’. Here realists rely on a version of what is sometimes referred to as the ‘all subjected principle’ of democratic theory.63 The basic structure of this principle is egalitarian, such that those who are subjected to an authority’s laws should have an equal say of some sort. Indeed, even Newey’s minimalist version, which merely requires an agreement that is ‘thought of as free’,64 presumes that every individual subject to the authority should perceive the agreement as free, rather than just a limited group of subjects within the citizenry. Even if the source of normativity in ‘free agreement follows from the conditions on collective action’,65 it does not follow that legitimacy requires political power to ‘be authorized by those on whose behalf the collective is taken to act’,66 unless some further normative premises are added.67 The above analysis finds that, on a closer look at the realists’ justification of political legitimacy, they all rely on some moral value(s). Hence political legitimacy is, in fact, irreducibly moral and, consequently, the moral domain does have a certain priority over the political domain in terms of a justificatory priority. Justificatory priority of morality over politics means that among the values that justify (a reasonable notion of) political legitimacy, moral values are at the core. Note that we are not saying that behind any value justifying political legitimacy there must be a moral value. Our claim is rather that, while non-moral values may play a justificatory role among the grounding values of political legitimacy, there are also moral values, which are tied either to the procedural or substantive features of political legitimacy. And this is true, we believe, not only of the accounts of current realists but of all (defensible) normative notions of political legitimacy. Even if we grant that it is a rather bold move to go from the accounts of political realists to all accounts of legitimacy, we think it is motivated. When realist accounts of legitimacy, given their aim of taking ‘political reality’ into account, also turn out to include moral values, there is simply not enough wiggle room left for a plausible account that does not include moral values of any sort. Without such values, it will always lack the sought-after normative force.

440

THE COMPATIBILITY THESIS: THE AUTONOMY OF THE POLITICAL

441

So far we have defended the ethics first premise. In this section we demonstrate that, contrary to the worry expressed by political realists, this premise is compatible with holding onto an autonomous political domain. We do so by distinguishing between a too

405 406 407 408 409 410 411 412 413 414 415 416 417 418 419 420 421 422 423 424 425 426 427 428 429 430 431 432 433 434 435 436 437 438

442 443

62

Williams 2005; cf. Erman 2009. See, for example, Dahl 1989; Habermas 1996. 64 Newey 2010, 460. 65 Newey 2010. 66 Newey 2010, 450. 67 And to the extent that these conditions are meant to be empirical, Newey would not offer a normative conception of political legitimacy to begin with. 63

Political Legitimacy in the Real Normative World

13

demanding type of autonomy of the political that seems to figure in the heads of political realists – what we call ‘hyperautonomy of the political’ (‘hyperautonomy’ for short) – and a thinner notion that reveals itself in the explicit charges they make against political moralists, what we call ‘basic autonomy of the political’ (‘basic autonomy’ for short). While the former does indeed violate the necessity thesis, the latter is fully compatible with it. In the last subsection, we further argue that it is possible to thicken and substantiate autonomy in many different ways beyond basic autonomy to more fully address questions such as political agency and collective decision making.

444

Hyperautonomy and More on the Relation between the Moral and the Political

452

An evaluation of the claim that the political domain would lack autonomy according to the ethics first view depends not only on what we mean by ‘the autonomy of the political’, but also on how we understand the relationship between the political and the moral. Let us start with hyperautonomy. According to this demanding notion, the normative source of political legitimacy lies exclusively within the political domain.68 Since we interpret the ethics first premise to entail that political legitimacy is justificatory dependent on moral values, and the ethics first premise is necessary to all reasonable accounts of political justification, it directly follows that hyperautonomy is unattainable.69 Note, however, that ‘unattainable’ wrongly signals that hyperautonomy would be the ideal that, unfortunately, cannot be reached. But as we have argued in the previous section, this is the very idea that realists should eschew. In order to fully appreciate this point, let us return to the distinction between the moral and the political domains, which we briefly explicated above. We concluded that the way realists use the terms, the moral domain typically concerns individual actions, whereas the political domain typically concerns collective actions and procedures pertaining to society’s basic institutions. Our main point has been that this difference in focus does not entail that the normative, justificatory grounding of legitimacy can be fully separated: moral values are also necessary in the political domain. In other words, we should refrain from conceiving of the moral and the political as entirely separate spheres, which realist expressions like ‘prior to’ and ‘external to’ might delude us into believing. An important reason why we hold on to the broad characterization of the two domains made by realists is precisely because our argument does not rely on any specific view of morality (which is why we use ‘morality’ and ‘ethics’ interchangeably). For example, we do not have to defend an individualist morality, as do liberal idealists. Also a more collectivistic approach to morality, according to which the ethico-cultural community is a prerequisite for possessing a moral language (such as communitarianism) uses the ethics first premise as a basis for construing and grounding political legitimacy.70 Further, our argument does not imply that the moral values that ground political legitimacy must be tied to a particular conception of justice or democracy. However, even in what Jeremy Waldron calls ‘the circumstances of politics’, which are permeated by radical

453

68

In Rossi’s words, a ‘freestanding account’ (Rossi 2012, 156). See also Rossi 2010, 204–12. Moreover, hyperautonomy’s ‘exclusivity’ criterion seems too strong even to allow Williams’ own response to the question of whether his notion of legitimacy is itself a moral principle: ‘If it is, it does not represent a morality which is prior to politics’ (Williams 2005, 5), since it demands that the domain of politics is fully independent of the moral domain. 70 For example, as argued by Walzer, the political community ought to reflect the self-understanding of the ethico-cultural community (Walzer 1984). 69

445 446 447 448 449 450 451

454 455 456 457 458 459 460 461 462 463 464 465 466 467 468 469 470 471 472 473 474 475 476 477 478 479 480 481 482

14

E R M A N A N D M O¨ L L E R

505

disagreement over matters of justice, moral values play an essential role in justifying political legitimacy.71 In addition, our argument does not presume any particular theory of moral justification. We have framed our normative discussion in terms of ‘moral values’ and ‘moral principles’ since, as we noted above, political realists typically do not deny grounding principles. However our argument is also compatible with doubts concerning the applicability of principles or the level of generality of principles. The fundamental claim is that the basic justification of political legitimacy includes moral considerations, whether or not it refers to general principles or values. Hence, our argument is compatible with claims that justification in the political domain need not come in the form of general principles that always hold. The basic justification of political legitimacy may be irreducibly contextual, so that we may not find a principle that always captures what is politically legitimate, no matter the situation.72 We take no stand as to whether or not this is possible – our argument is merely that, even in this case, moral considerations will figure into the justification (which is why our necessity thesis is not also a ‘sufficiency thesis’). Hence our argument is also valid for those who claim that justification – when it comes in the form of principles – comes in the form of contextual principles that are inherently bound to the institutional structures to which they are supposed to apply, rather than in the form of abstract, general ones.73 As we have stressed throughout, while theorists disagree on how big a role contextual factors – such as historical traditions, narratives of a polity, held values, etc. – play in the justification of political legitimacy, our claim merely states that as long as the justification is supposed to have normative force (as in the current debate), moral values are necessary.

506

Basic Autonomy

507

Thus hyperautonomy is an implausible notion. But looking more closely at the criticism that realists actually put forward, the thinner notion of basic autonomy reveals itself through the explicit charges made against political moralism:

483 484 485 486 487 488 489 490 491 492 493 494 495 496 497 498 499 500 501 502 503 504

508 509 510 511 512 513 514 515 516 517 518 519 520 521

1) that politics is construed as an arena for the realization of moral principles (for example, Galston, Rossi) 2) that political normativity is reduced to morality (for example, Newey) 3) that moral reasons trump all other kinds of reasons when deciding what is politically legitimate (for example, Newey) Basic autonomy is thus the rejection of these three propositions. However, the ethics first premise is in fact compatible with basic autonomy. To demonstrate this, let us take a look at each of these propositions. The first is arguably the most rhetoric of the three, since we wonder whether any political theorist conceives of the political domain merely in these terms. Certainly Rawls, the main target of the realist critique, does not. More importantly for the present article, however, the first proposition definitely does not follow from the ethics first 71

Waldron 1999. For a recent debate about political legitimacy and disagreement on justice under nonideal circumstances, see Mason 2010; Mason 2012; Sleat 2012. Note also that even notions of the moral domain that primarily focus on individual action often mention a broader context. See, for example, Brink 2001, 174. 72 See Hooker and Little 2000, 165–84. 73 See, for example, so-called practice-dependent accounts in political theory: Rossi 2012; Sangiovanni 2008; Sangiovanni 2011.

Political Legitimacy in the Real Normative World

15

premise. Even if moral principles and values, such as fundamental egalitarian ones, figure into the basic justification of any normative account of political legitimacy, there are numerous other tasks that are also part of politics. And if the political domain includes institutional aspects and practical concerns that do not follow from the moral justificatory basis – which is a necessary aspect of political justification – the political domain is not merely an arena for realizing moral principles. The second proposition takes us explicitly into the normative sphere. While normativity comes in many varieties (for example, semantic, epistemic, aesthetical), the relevant sense here is practical – that is, practical normativity primarily concerns how we should act. As explicated above, realist accounts typically distinguish between moral and political values and principles. The second charge claims that political normativity is reduced to morality in the political moralist view. Admittedly, this is a possible theoretical position. Some influential moral theorists indeed interpret the basic normative term ‘ought’ as merely expressing what we should do, all things considered.74 Doing so would arguably reduce all practical normativity to morality.75 However, this reductive view does not in any sense follow from the ethics first premise. On the contrary, most contemporary philosophers are skeptical of the possibly of reducing one domain of discourse to another, and among moral theorists it is much more common to acknowledge a variety of different types of non-moral considerations – political, prudential, altruistic, egotistical, instrumental – and to deny rather than defend the claim that all normativity is reduced to morality.76 Above all, we have found no textual support that political moralists would in fact embrace such a strong and controversial reduction claim. The third proposition seems to be the only one that comes close to being incompatible with the view of some moral theorists. The idea that moral reasons trump other kinds of reasons does, indeed, have its followers.77 But as with the previous claims, it is far from obligatory. If anything, many moral theorists reject that moral reasons always trump other reasons.78 Crucially, however, whether or not moral reasons trump other kinds of reasons lacks relevance for the issue at hand. For even if we assume that moral reasons trump other kinds of reasons – so that if there is a conclusive moral reason to f, then we should f regardless of what other reasons (here: political) we have for doing something else. This fact does not entail that moral reasons decide what is politically legitimate. On the contrary, the trumping claim implies that political reasons are distinct from moral reasons (since otherwise political reasons would, by necessity, be aligned with moral ones). In general, we cannot expect two distinct concepts to have the same extension.79 Thus just as something may be a kind act even though it is not morally right, we should expect that a decision could be politically legitimate even if it is not morally right. Indeed, the very notion of justificatory dependence that we have defended opens this possibility, since we claim here that moral values are necessary (but not sufficient) for political legitimacy. 74

See, for example, Gibbard 2003; Wedgwood 2001. In fact, even this may be too strong a claim. Theorists like Gibbard and Wedgewood could also be interpreted as being silent about reduction, merely making a claim about the extension of the moral ought. 76 For characterizations see, for example, Brink 1998; Foot 1959; Jackson 1998. 77 In moral philosophy, a reason is a consideration that speaks in favor of having a belief, performing an action, etc. If (but not necessarily only if) a reason is constituted by moral values or principles, we count it as a moral reason. See Parfit 1997; Scanlon 1998. 78 Hume 1998; Parfit 2011; Sidgwick 1874. 79 Even if they may, as in the classical case of ‘creatures with kidneys’ and ‘creatures with a heart’. 75

522 523 524 525 526 527 528 529 530 531 532 533 534 535 536 537 538 539 540 541 542 543 544 545 546 547 548 549 550 551 552 553 554 555 556 557 558 559 560

16

E R M A N A N D M O¨ L L E R

579

The upshot is that political reasons may trump moral reasons in political decision making, and that political outcomes may be legitimately amoral or even immoral. Whether this is so will depend on what is decided upon, what moral and other reasons are involved, and what kind of decision it is. For example, say that we ground political legitimacy in the moral value of equal worth, specifying this value in terms of the equal consideration of everyone’s interest. Moral reasons pleading to this value would most likely trump political reasons used against it (for example in support of the political selfdetermination of a specific religious or ethnic group) if the decision concerned fundamental constitutional matters (for example basic rights of the members of the polity). However, even concerning such matters, not all moral reasons would trump, since other moral values (for example, individual freedom), might be set aside in favor of specifically political values (for example, universal suffrage), if, say, voting was mandatory. By the same token, decisions to give financial state support to a sexist political party or allow a racist political demonstration might be justified by political reasons (for example, by valuing political competition and opposition or the freedom of assembly). These reasons are all regarded as indispensible sources of normativity in a democratic polity, even though there are strong moral reasons – from the standpoint of the equal concern of everyone’s interest – to deny support and to prevent these protesters from shouting disparaging and insulting remarks about certain groups in society.

580

Beyond Basic Autonomy

581

On the one hand, realists (wrongly) accuse political moralism of failing to embrace basic autonomy. On the other, it is quite clear that realists hope for something more substantial than basic autonomy in theorizing political legitimacy. So what are realists worried about with regard to the autonomy of the political? Foremost, they seem worried that the ethics first premise leads to depoliticization in the sense that the political domain is deprived of any real political agents, and that political moralism cannot offer any plausible account of political agency. One reason for this is that since politics concerns public reasons, there is no general way to construct political agency from individual reasons for action alone.80 However, that the political is collectively autonomous in this way does not imply that it is not an individual political practice as well. In their eagerness to see the moral domain as the arena concerned with individual action and the political domain as the arena concerned with collective action, realists neglect that political legitimacy is premised on both individual and collective autonomy and thus involves individual and collective agency. Acknowledging both these dimensions, together with the conclusion that basic autonomy is a property of any reasonable conception of political legitimacy, opens up considerable room for moving beyond basic autonomy in the theorizing of political legitimacy. Let us conclude by looking at how this could be done. Contrary to what realists may lead us to believe, the problem with basic autonomy is not that it leaves too little space for a substantive account of autonomy; it leaves a fairly large space. The problem is rather that this space has thus far been relatively unexplored and left empty of theoretical content. Indeed, it is here that the realist critique of political moralism hits the target, articulated for example in terms of undertheorized notions of political agency and collective self-determination. From the point of view of our metatheoretical argument, it is possible to substantiate and justify legitimacy in numerous ways from sources of normativity specifically from

561 562 563 564 565 566 567 568 569 570 571 572 573 574 575 576 577 578

582 583 584 585 586 587 588 589 590 591 592 593 594 595 596 597 598 599 600 601 602 603 604

80

Bellamy 2010; Newey 2010; Philp 2010.

Political Legitimacy in the Real Normative World

17

within the political, since the only requirement dictated by the ethics first premise on a justificatory reading is that this is not its only source. We hold that it is precisely within the framework set by the ethics first premise that political realists can (and should) perform conceptual and normative work that takes the debate forward. In fact, not only does it lead to a dead end conceptually to go outside of this framework; by working explicitly within it, realists will also avoid setting the bar so low for political legitimacy that most countries in the world today are already above the threshold by a good margin. Needless to say, to solely require of political power that it be ‘not entirely tyrannical’ or ‘not entirely suppressive’ in order to be legitimate means to demand less of legitimacy than, say, even Zimbabweans would expect from Mugabe. We see no reason why realists would want to do that. One possible explanation of why realists are satisfied with such a low bar is that they try as hard as they can to deny the ethics first premise. But to effectively and convincingly substantiating the notion of autonomy, realists must not only acknowledge the ethics first premise but also further unpack the necessary conditions implied by basic autonomy and thus their particular version of this premise. This would mean to make explicit, rather than rebuff, the moral values embedded in their agreement and autonomy conditions. For example, what notion of equality is involved in each of them and how does a bar as low as ‘not entirely tyrannical’ or ‘not entirely suppressive’ fare with it? Up until today, realists have been so preoccupied with finding faults with political moralism that they have wrongly assumed that the political domain, in order to be autonomous, must somehow be separated and ‘rescued’ from morality when theorizing political legitimacy – hence the use of terms such as ‘prior to’ or ‘external to’ – instead of exploring overlapping sources of normativity. Since political legitimacy concerns institutions and authority in the political domain, and politics irreducibly concerns collective decision making, both individual and collective aspects of autonomy are central for normative reasons. Therefore, moving beyond basic autonomy would require that we explore in tandem what values (moral and other) underpin both individual reasons for action and individual agency (for example, individual freedom and equal consideration) and public reasons for action (for example, collective decision making and self-determination).

605

REFERENCES

634

Bavister-Gould, Alex. 2011. Bernard Williams: Political Realism and the Limits of Legitimacy. European Journal of Philosophy. Early online view. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0378.2011.00464.x. Bellamy, Richard. 2010. Dirty Hands and Clean Gloves: Liberal Ideals and Real Politics. European Journal of Political Theory 9:412–30. Brandom, Robert. 1994. Making it Explicit. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Brink, David. 1998. Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——. 2001. Realism, Naturalism, and Moral Semantics. Social Philosophy & Policy 18:154–76. Dahl, Robert. 1989. Democracy and its Critics. New Haven: Yale University Press. Erman, Eva. 2009. What is Wrong with Agonistic Pluralism? Reflections on Conflict in Democratic Theory. Philosophy & Social Criticism 35:1039–62. Erman, Eva, and Niklas Mo¨ller. 2013. Three Failed Charges Against Ideal Theory. Social Theory & Practice 39:19–44. Estlund, David. 2008. Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework. New Jersey: Princeton University Press. ——. 2011. Human Nature and the Limits (If Any) of Political Philosophy. Philosophy & Public Affairs 39:207–37.

635

606 607 608 609 610 611 612 613 614 615 616 617 618 619 620 621 622 623 624 625 626 627 628 629 630 631 632 633

636 637 638 639 640 641 642 643 644 645 646 647 648 649 650 651

18 652 653 654 655 656 657 658 659 660 661 662 663 664 665 666 667 668 669 670 671 672 673 674 675 676 677 678 679 680 681 682 683 684 685 686 687 688 689 690 691 692 693 694 695 696 697 698 699 700 701 702 703

E R M A N A N D M O¨ L L E R

Farrelly, Colin. 2007. Justice in Ideal Theory: A Refutation. Political Studies 55:844–64. Foot, Philippa. 1959. Moral Beliefs. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 59:83–104. Galston, William. 2010. Realism in Political Theory. European Journal of Political Theory 9:385–411. Geuss, Raymond. 2008. Philosophy and Real Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Gibbard, Allan. 2003. Thinking How to Live. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Habermas, Ju¨rgen. 1996. Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Translated by William Rehg. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Honig, Bonnie. 1993. Political Theory and the Displacement of Politics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Hooker, Brad, and Margaret Little. 2000. Moral Particularism. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Horton, John. 2010. Realism, Liberal Moralism and a Political Theory of Modus Vivendi. European Journal of Political Theory 9:431–48. Hume, David. 1998. An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, edited by Tom Beauchamp. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hurka, Thomas. 2009. Review of Geuss’s Philosophy and Real Politics. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews No. 1, January. Available from http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/23887-philosophy-and-realpolitics/, accessed 13 April 2013. Jackson, Frank. 1998. From Ethics to Metaphysics: A Defence of Conceptual Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Mason, Andrew. 2010. Rawlsian Theory and the Circumstances of Politics. Political Theory 38:658–83. ——. 2012. Legitimacy and Disagreement: A Reply to Sleat. Political Theory 40:657–62. Mills, Charles. 2005. ‘Ideal Theory’ as Ideology. Hypathia 20:165–84. Mouffe, Chantal. 2005. On the Political. London: Routledge. Newey, Glen. 2010. Two Dogmas of Liberalism. European Journal of Political Theory 9:449–65. Parfit, Derek. 1997. Reasons and Motivation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, (suppl. 71):99–130. ——. 2011. On What Matters, Vol. I. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Philp, Mark. 2007. Political Conduct. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ——. 2010. What is to be Done? Political Theory and Political Realism. European Journal of Political Theory 9:466–84. ——. 2012. Realism without Illusions. Political Theory 40:629–49. Rachels, James. 1999. The Elements of Moral Philosophy. New York: McGraw-Hill. Ross, William D. 1930. The Right and the Good. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rossi, Enzo. 2010. Reality and Imagination in Political Theory and Practice: On Raymond Geuss’ Realism. European Journal of Political Theory 9:204–12. ——. 2012. Justice, Legitimacy and (Normative) Authority for Political Realists. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 15:149–64. Sangiovanni, Andrea. 2008. Justice and the Priority of Politics to Morality. Journal of Political Philosophy 16:137–64. ——. 2011. Global Justice and the Moral Arbitrariness of Birth. The Monist 94:571–83. Scanlon, Thomas. 1998. What We Owe To Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Sen, Amartya. 2009. The Idea of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Sidgwick, Henry. 1874. The Methods of Ethics. London: Macmillan. Simmons, John. 2010. Ideal and Nonideal Theory. Philosophy & Public Affairs 38:5–36. Sleat, Matt. 2010. Bernard Williams and the Possibility of a Realist Political Theory. European Journal of Political Theory 9:485–503. ——. 2012. Legitimacy in a Non-Ideal Key: A Critical Response to Andrew Mason. Political Theory 40:650–6. Stears, Marc. 2007. Review Article: Liberalism and the Politics of Compulsion. British Journal of Political Science 37:505–31. Valentini, Laura. 2009. On the Apparent Paradox of Ideal Theory. The Journal of Political Philosophy 17:332–55.

Political Legitimacy in the Real Normative World

19

Waldron, Jeremy. 1999. Law and Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Walzer, Michael. 1984. Spheres of Justice. New York: Basic Books. Wedgwood, Ralph. 2001. Conceptual Role Semantics for Moral Terms. Philosophical Review 110:1–30. Wiggins, David. 1990. Moral Cognitivism, Moral Relativism and Motivating Moral Beliefs. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91:61–85. Williams, Bernard. 1985. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. London: Fontana. ——. 2005. In the Beginning Was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument, edited by Geoffrey Hawthorn. Oxford: Princeton University Press.

704 705 706 707 708 709 710 711 712