Situated creativity, contingency and modernity: an ...

1 downloads 0 Views 144KB Size Report
I say that the model of normatively oriented action is more comprehensive ... do. For example, I may think that peace is an important value, but let's say ..... he says— the Jewish value of Justice or the Christian value of Love have come into.
Situated  creativity,  contingency  and  modernity:  an  interview  with   Hans  Joas     Hans  Joas  -­‐  Pablo  Beytía  

 

Translated  section  of:  Beytía,  Pablo  (2012).  Creatividad  situada,  contingencia  y   modernidad.  Entrevista  a  Hans  Joas.  Andamios,  Nº  12,  pp.  361-­‐389.  

      Pablo  Beytía:  Let  me  start  this  interview  with  a  general  question  about  the  theory  of   action.   With   influences   from   historicism,   hermeneutics   and   pragmatism,   you   have   criticized  the  rationalistic  and  normativistic  theories,  and  proposed  a  unified  theory  of   practice  based  on  creativity,  on  the  "situated  freedom"  of  the  human  being.  What  are   the   theoretical   problems   that   you   identified   in   the   earlier   action   theories   and   how   can   the  emphasis  on  creativity  overcome  them?     Hans   Joas:   In   the   history   of   sociological   theorizing,   or   one   might   even   say,   in   the   history  of  social  scientific  theorizing,  there  has  been  for  more  than  hundred  years  a   constant   controversy   between   those   who   propose   models   of   rational   action   and   those  who  criticize  these  economic  types  of  theorizing,  mostly  by  emphasizing  the   normative   character   of   human   action.   I   think   this   is   a   controversy   that   you   can   identify,   for   example,   in   Émile   Durkheim's   critique   of   Herbert   Spencer   in   his   book   The   Division   of   Labor   in   Society1   or   in   Talcott   Parsons'   book   of   1937  The   Structure   of   Social   Action,2   but   also   in   the   1980s,   when   Amitai   Etzioni   wrote   the   book  The   Moral   Dimension,3  which  is  a  critique  of  the  microeconomic  model.     I   accept   most   of   the   objections   these   normativists   have   raised   against   the   rational   action   model.   I   think   that   rational   action   is   the   narrowest   model   for   understanding   human   action,   because   we   all   know   that   only   a   very   small   amount   of   human  actions  empirically  fit  the  description  of  rational  action.  Most  proponents  of   the   rational   action   model   would   agree   with   that   and   say:   “Yes,   of   course   empirically   only   very   few   actions   are   rational   actions.   But,   nevertheless,   this   model,   for   other   reasons,  is  the  most  useful  to  conceptualize  action”.       Now,   what   the   normativists   —from   Durkheim   through   Parsons   and   up   to   Etzioni—   say,   is   that   rational   action   models   have   two   main   problems:   One   is   that   they   cannot   explain   where   the   normativity,   which   is   an   element   of   the   notion   of   rationality,   comes   from.   And,   secondly,   they   have   problems   explaining   the   existence   of   stabilized   social   order.   This   was   the   argumentation   in   Parsons'   The   Structure   of   Social  Action.       Furthermore,   we   all   know   that   we   live   within   a   social   order   and   that   this   social   order   is   more   than   the   result   of   the   aggregations   of   rational   action.   In   that                                                                                                                  

1  Durkheim,  Émile.  1893.  De  la  Division  du  Travail  Social.  Paris:  Presses  Universitaires  de  France.   2  Parsons,  Talcott.  1937.  The  Structure  of  Social  Action.  New  York:  McGraw  Hill.   3  Etzioni,  Amitai.  1988.  The  Moral  Dimension.  Toward  a  new  economics.  New  York:  The  Free  Press.  

sense,   the   model   of   normatively   oriented   action   is   wider   than   the   rational   action   model,   because   it   tries   to   explain   the   existence   of   normative   social   order   and   the   emergence  of  norms,  including  the  normative  character  of  rationality.       When   you   say   rationality,   you   use   it   as   a   normative   concept   in   itself.   For   example,   in   the   history   of   economic   theorizing,   one   of   the   great   books   is   Albert   Hirschman's   study   The   Passions   and   the   Interests,4   which   showed   that   in   the   history   of   economic   theorizing,   rationality   meant   not   simply   the   release   of   your   spontaneous   corporeal   desires,   but   a   control   over   these   desires   to   act   as   a   truly   economic   actor.   And   so,   we   have   this   ambiguity   in   the   understanding   of   rational   action:  whether  it  means  just  following  your  desires  or  whether  it  means  controlling   your   desires   with   long-­‐term   rational   goals   in   mind.   For   example,   accumulating   wealth  instead  of  just  spending  all  the  money  that  you  earn  or  that  you  have.  In  that   sense,   rational   action   itself   has   a   normative   character,   but   you   cannot   explain   the   quality   of   this   normativity   within   the   terminology   of   rational   action   theory.   That   was  Parsons'  argument  in  The  Structure  of  Social  Action  (1937),  that  I  regard  as  his   greatest  and  most  important  book.       I   say   that   the   model   of   normatively   oriented   action   is   more   comprehensive   and   that   it   is   able   to   solve   two   problems   that   cannot   be   solved   by   means   of   the   rational   action   theory.   Now,   the   model   of   the   creativity   of   action   is   even   more   comprehensive,   because   the   normatively   oriented   models   cannot   explain   two   things:   one   is   how   we   apply   norms   and   values   in   concrete   situations   of   action.   Even   if  we  have  internalized  specific  norms  or  values,  it  is  not  necessarily  clear  how  we   have  to  act.  We  cannot  logically  derive  from  our  norms  and  values  what  we  have  to   do.   For   example,   I   may   think   that   peace   is   an   important   value,   but   let's   say   somewhere   in   the   world   a   civil   war   breaks   out   or   let's   say   in   my   country   a   civil   war   breaks  out.  What  do  I  have  to  do  when  I  believe  in  peace?  Does  that  mean  that  I  have   to   be   a   radical   pacifist   who   says:   “I   will   never   use   means   of   violence,   whatever   happens,  I  will  not  use  means  of  violence,  even  if  I'm  being  attacked,  I  will  not  use   violence  to  defend  myself”.  It  would  be  one  possible  conclusion.  Of  course  another   possible  conclusion  is  to  say:  “Since  I  believe  in  peace,  I  have  to  fight  for  a  peaceful   order   to   repress   those   who   have   taken   up   arms”.   And,   in   this   situation,   I   will   maybe   use   weapons   for   the   sake   of   peace.   So,   the   mere   fact   that   I   believe   in   the   value   of   peace  does  not  really  tell  me  what  I  have  to  do,  because  there  can  be  totally  different   courses  of  action  that  are  based  on  the  same  value.     For   the   solution   of   that   problem   —for   an   adequate   description   of   how   our   actions   are   based   on   our   norms   and   values—,   we   need   a   creativity-­‐oriented   understanding   of   action,   because   our   courses   of   action   are   always   risky.   Even   if   I   think  that  I  am  doing  something  with  a  distinct  goal  in  mind,  I  can  never  be  sure  that   this   is   really   the   action   that   leads   me   to   achieve   that   end,   because   action   is   future   oriented  and  I  cannot  anticipate  the  things  that  may  pervert  the  course  of  my  action.   So  this  is  one  of  the  two  problems  of  a  normative  theory  that  the  theory  of  creative   action  can  solve.                                                                                                                  

4  Hirschman,  Albert.  1977.  The  Passions  and  the  Interests:  political  arguments  for  capitalism  before  its   triumph.  New  Jersey:  Princeton  University  Press.  

  The  second  one  is  the  origin  of  values.5  Normatively  oriented  action  theory,   like  the  one  Parsons  developed,  constantly  speaks  about  values,  but  it  has  no  answer   to  the  question  where  these  values  come  from.  I  think  Durkheim  is  a  different  case,   because   I   personally   think   that   his   book   on   religion,   The   Elementary   Forms   of   Religious  Life,6  is  one  of  the  most  important  contributions  to  an  understanding  of  the   emergence  of  values,  in  experiences  that  I  call  self-­‐transcendence.     In   that   sense,   the   creativity   oriented   model   of   action   is   the   most   comprehensive,   more   comprehensive   than   the   rational   action   model   and   than   the   normatively   oriented   model   of   action.   But   be   careful:   It   would   be   wrong   to   think   that  we  are  talking  about  three  types  of  action  here:  I'm  talking  about  three  types  of   action   theory,   not   three   types   of   action.   And   what   I   am   emphasizing   is   the   distinction  between  these  three  types  of  action  theory.  So,  I  am  not  talking  about  a   type   of   creative   action,   but   about   a   theory   of   the   creativity   of   action   that   is   also   necessary  to  understand  rational  action  and  normatively  oriented  action.       P.  B.:  A  unified  theory  of  action…  Is  this  the  same  problem  that  Parsons  attempted  to   resolve?     H.  J.:  Yes,  it  was  Parsons’  problem,  but  I  think  Parsons'  model  has  remained  within   the   range   of   the   alternative   between   rational   and   normatively   oriented   action,   whereas  some  of  the  sociological  classics,  above  all  Durkheim,  to  some  extent  also   Max   Weber   and   Georg   Simmel   —I   have   written   about   that   in   the   beginning   of   the   book   The   creativity   of   action—,7   and   mostly   American   pragmatism   and   the   hermeneutic   historicist   tradition   have   contributed   to   the   understanding   of   the   creativity  of  action.     P.   B.:   One   criticism   to   your   theory   has   been   (I   am   thinking   of   Charles   Camic8   and   Rafael   Farfán)9   that   its   focus   on   creativity   hides   the   importance   of   certain   types   of   actions,   such   as   imitation,   habit   or   routine.   This   could   prevent   that   your   theory   is   conceived   as   a   unified   proposal   for   action   theory.   Is   it   possible   to   understand   the   creative  action  in  these  practices?     H.   J.:   One   of   Charles   Camic's   articles,   the   one   on   habit   in   the   American   Journal   of   sociology10  many  years  ago,  makes  a  point  that  is  quite  similar  to  what  I  am  saying.   You  have  to  understand  that  my  theory  of  the  creativity  of  action  is  not  a  theory  of   creative   action.   Opposing   habit   to   creative   action   is   something   totally   different,   of   course.                                                                                                                    

5   On   this   topic,   see:   Joas,   Hans.   1997.   Die   Entstehung   der   Werte.   Frankfurt:   Suhrkamp.   (English   translation:  The  Genesis  of  Values.  Chicago:  University  of  Chicago  Press  2000).   6  Durkheim,  Émile.  1998.   Élémentaires  Formes  de  la  Vie  Religieuse:  le  Système  Totémique  en  Australie.   Presses  Universitaires  de  France.   7  Joas,  Hans.  1992.  Die  Kreativität  des  Handelns.  Frankfurt:  Suhrkamp.   8  Camic,  Charles.  1998.  “Reconstructing  the  theory  of  action”.  Sociological  Theory,  Vol  3,  Nº  16.   9  Farfán,  Rafael.  1999.  “Ni  acción  ni  sistema:  el  tercer  modelo  de  acción  de  Hans  Joas”.  Sociológica,  Nº   40.   10  Camic,  Charles.  1986.  “The  matter  of  habit”.  American  Journal  of  Sociology,  Vol.  91,  Nº  5.  

  Like   the   classical   pragmatists,   I   say   that   for   the   understanding   of   human   action   habit   is   crucial.   That   was   one   of   the   crucial   points   in   the   writings   of   the   pragmatists;  they  said  that  human  action  to  a  very  large  extent  is  habitual.  And  yes,   of  course  we  act  on  the  basis  of  routines.  I  could  not  survive  for  five  minutes  without   routines.   For   example,   the   way   I   walk   around   is   totally   habitual:   I   once   learned   how   to  walk,  when  I  was  about  one  year  old,  and,  since  then,  it  has  become  a  corporeal   habit.  I  do  not  have  to  think  about  how  to  walk,  I  just  do  it.       That   is   the   basic   pragmatist   idea,   as   long   as   I   do   not   encounter   a   problem.   When  I  encounter  a  problem  —for  example,  I  walk,  but  suddenly  there  is  a  river  and   there  is  no  bridge  but  I  want  to  get  to  the  other  side  of  the  river,  thus  I  encounter  an   obstacle   because   I   cannot   just   continue   walking—,   I   search   a   solution.   So,   in   the   pragmatist  way  of  thinking,  our  action  takes  place  in  a  constant  tension  between  our   habits  and  anticipating  problems  for  which  we  have  to  find  creative  solutions.       So   my   model   of   action   is   not   a   model   of   constant   creativity,   but   of   habitual   action  and  creativity,  applied  in  situations  where  the  routines  get  into  some  kind  of   crisis:   when   I   have   a   problem,   when   I   cannot   just   continue.   That   is   the   understanding   of   the   creativity   of   action   that   I   have   developed   in   my   book   twenty   years   ago.   I   think   that   it   just   does   not   make   sense   to   say:   —“but   where   are   the   habits?   You   just   talk   about   creativity”—,   because   I   am   not   just   talking   about   creativity,  but  about  the  interplay  between  habits  and  creativity.  You  could  say  that   on   the   basis   of   a   theory   of   the   creativity   of   human   action,   you   can   reach   an   appropriate  understanding  of  what  habit  is.  Habit  is  a  central  notion  in  the  theory  of   the  creativity  of  human  action.     P.   B.:   Distantly   influenced   by   pragmatism   (Pascal,   Marx,   Bachelard,   etc.),   Bourdieu   also   poses   an   escape   from   the   philosophy   of   consciousness.   He   designs   a   nonteleological   action   theory   that   emphasizes   the   corporeality   of   the   actor   and   his   original   sociality.   Despite   these   remarkable   coincidences,   I   think   there   is   a   fundamental   difference   between   Bourdieu's   focus   and   your   focus:   Bourdieu's   theory   of   practice   places   great   emphasis   on   the   dispositions   recorded   in   the   agents   and   the   society,   while   you   emphasize   —if   I   understand   you   correctly—   the   creative   solution   of   problems   encountered   in   habitual   situations.   Do   you   think   that   both   theories   are   contradictory?  Could  the  two  approaches  complement  each  other?     H.  J.:  Let  me  say  three  things.  The  first  is  that  if  you  want  my  extensive  response  to   your  question,  you  should  look  at  the  Bourdieu  chapter  in  the  book  Social  theory.11   There   you   will   see   much   better   a   detailed   critique   of   Bourdieu   than   what   I   can   spontaneously  develop  now.     Second  point,  I  am  not  sure  that  Bourdieu  and  I  describe  the  problem  in  the   same  terms.  I  think  that  Bourdieu,  as  a  French  thinker,  was  very  much  thinking  in   terms   of   an   alternative   to   phenomenology   and   structuralism.   His   claim   is   to   have                                                                                                                   11  Joas,  Hans  and  Wolfgang  Knöbl.  2004.  Sozialtheorie:  zwanzig  einführende  Vorlesungen.  Frankfurt:   Suhrkamp,   pp.   510-­‐557   (Fünfzehnte   Vorlesung).   (English   translation:   Social   Theory.   Twenty   Introductory   Lectures.   Cambridge:   Cambridge   University   Press   2009.   Spanish   translation   forthcoming).  

developed   a   kind   of   synthesis   of   elements   from   phenomenology   and   from   structuralism,   or   to   have   gone   beyond   that   dichotomy.   In   his   early   days,   he   once   published   a   very   interesting   article   on   the   vacillation   of   French   intellectual   life   between  a  kind  of  extreme  emphasis  on  subjectivity,  for  example  in  Phenomenology,   and  an  extreme  emphasis  on  objectivity,  for  example  in  Structuralism.  I  think  that  is   correct   with   regard   to   the   French   intellectual   traditions,   but   it   is   not   correct,   for   example,  with  regard  to  the  German  or  American  intellectual  traditions.       So,  in  that  sense,  I  would  not  accept  Bourdieu's  description  of  the  intellectual   situation,  but  I  would  say  that  he  overgeneralizes  something  that  is  true  for  France,   but   not   true   for   other   countries.   And   this   is   important,   because   the   traditions   on   which   my   own   thinking   is   based   do   not   really   fit   into   his   description.   I   think   neither   Pragmatism   nor   Hermeneutics   are   extreme   subjectivism   or   extreme   objectivism.   I   think  his  claim  for  originality  has  a  lot  to  do  with  his  description  of  the  intellectual   situation  in  France,  as  being  the  general  situation.  I  mean  if  you  look  at  his  work,  I   see  it  as  much  less  innovative  than  others  see  it,  because  I  think  many  things  he  says   were   already   articulated   by   the   American   and   German   traditions   long   before   Bourdieu  was  even  born.  For  example,  his  emphasis  on  habit  may  be  something  new   within  the  French  debate,  but  it  is  certainly  not  new  in  the  American  debate,  where   you  already  have  that  in  the  19th  century.       So   my   third   point   is   that   Bourdieu   emphasizes   the   habitual   character   of   action  and  he  emphasizes  corporeality,  no  question.  I  would  say  that  we  share  that,   but   I   doubt   that   he   has   an   understanding   of   the   creativity   of   human   action.   For   example,   an   interesting   case   is   to   look   at   his   book   on   art,   Les   règles   de   l'art.12   In   that   book  he  has  a  lot  of  interesting  things  to  say  about  the  conditions  for  the  production   of   art.   For   example,   how   a   man   writing   a   novel   anticipates   the   conditions   for   his   success,   when   he   publishes   a   book   or   how   he   distinguishes   himself   from   other   writers   and   all   these   things.   But   I   think   that   when   you   read   that,   you   also   realize,   that  although  all  these  conditions  may  be  true  and  although  they  are  all  important   and  all  interesting,  they  are  clearly  not  at  the  core  of  what  artistic  production  is.  You   may  have  a  complete  knowledge  of  the  conditions  for  the  success  of  a  novelist,  but   still  be  completely  unable  to  write  a  good  novel.  Because,  to  write  a  good  novel  or  to   create   an   important   new   painting,   you   need   certain   creative   abilities   that   are   totally   different  from  all  these  external  conditions  of  success.  I  think  that  right  at  that  point,   you  can  see  that  Bourdieu  had  a  sociological  approach  to  analyze  what  happens  to   creative   innovations,   but   has   no   understanding   of   the   action   that   is   adequate   for   these  creative  processes  themselves.     P.  B.:  We  come  back  to  the  concept  of  action...  I  think  it  is  a  broad  concept  that  —as   Talcott   Parsons   and   then   Niklas   Luhmann   pointed   out—,   crosses   the   boundaries   of   sociology.   Every   human   action   is   intertwined   with   biological,   psychological,   social   and   cultural   phenomena,   which   makes   action   a   category   of   interdisciplinary   study.   We   could   go   even   further   and   think   that   all   sciences,   in   describing   aspects   of   the   world,   also   describe   conditions   of   action.   What   then   distinguishes   sociology   from   other   sciences?  Must  sociology  study  a  specific  problem?  Is  there  a  social  object  that  should                                                                                                                   12  Bourdieu,  Pierre.  1992.  Les  règles  de  l'art:  genèse  et  structure  du  champ  littéraire.  Paris:  Seuil.  

be   fully   investigated   by   the   sociologist   (social   action,   social   fact,   interaction,   intersubjectivity,  communication,  relationship,  social  network,  etc.)?     H.   J.:   The   first   thing   is   that   for   a   long   time   sociologists   tried   to   define   the   subject   matter  of  their  discipline  as  society  and  I  am  very  skeptical  about  that.  I  think  that   had   something   to   do   with   the   fact   that   in   the   late   19th   and   early   20th   centuries,   in   Europe   above   all,   one   could   really   identify   societies   with   clear   cut   borders   and   imagine,   like   in   the   case   of   Durkheim,   that   sociology   in   France   studies   French   society   and   that   French   society   somehow   is   a   self-­‐contained   whole.   Now,   this   was   not  the  case  in  the  age  before  the  rise  of  the  nation-­‐state  and  it  is  certainly  much  less   the  case  in  the  contemporary  world,  where  so  many  economic,  political  and  cultural   processes  transcend  borders.  In  that  sense,  I  think  society  should  not  be  the  defining   word  for  the  discipline  of  sociology.       Now,   you   could   say   there   are   two   different   levels:   one   that   is   more   comprehensive   and   one   that   is   more   elementary   than   national   states   and   their   societies.   On   the   one   hand,   you   can   say   global   processes,   and   on   the   other   hand,   the   elementary  processes  of  social  life.  And  so,  our  book  Social  Theory13  uses  the  term   social   theory   and   not   sociological   theory   for   that   reason.   If   you   think   social   processes   are   the   subject   matter   of   sociology,   then   —as   you   said—   knowledge   from   other   disciplines   has   to   come   in   to   analyze   these   social   processes.   So,   for   me,   Sociology  is  not  defined  by  the  subject  matter  of  society,  but  by  social  processes.       Of   course,   in   order   to   explain   what   that   means,   you   have   to   introduce   a   specific   understanding   of   sociality.   When   you   use   the   term   social   action,   it   is   difficult,   because   this   concept   is   understood   in   very   different   ways   by   different   authors.  In  Max  Weber,  social  action  is  just  one  part  of  human  action  —those  actions   that   are   more   or   less   directly   addressed   to   other   actors—,   whereas   in   George   Herbert   Mead,   social   action   means   a   rich   group   process.   In   this   sense,   I   am   more   on   the  Meadian  than  on  the  Weberian  side.  In  other  regards,  I  am  much  closer  to  Max   Weber,   because   I   think   that   contemporary   sociology   has   to   renew   itself   through   historical   analyses,   something   that   Weber   and   Durkheim   did.   Mainly,   Sociology   should   not   restrict   itself   to   the   analysis   of   contemporary   social   processes,   but   to   bring   in   the   whole   of   world   history   and   use   universal   history   as   the   basis   for   its   theoretical   claims.   This   is   really   something   that   both   Weber   and   Durkheim   did,   they   did  not  just  speak  about  their  own  times,  but  about  human  history  in  the  long  run.   And   I   think   that   is   one   of   most   important   contemporary   developments   in   Sociology,   to  get  truly  historical  again.       P.  B.:  So  the  difference  between  sociology  and  other  sciences  would  be  one  object,  and   that  object  is  the  social  process.  Or  is  there  not  really  an  important  difference  between   disciplines?     H.  J.:  I  mean  I  understand  your  question  —mainly  is  it  a  perspective  or  is  it  a  subject   matter,   that   is   how   I   understand   your   question—.   Now   I   should   tell   you   that   in   a                                                                                                                  

13  Joas,  Hans  and  Wolfgang  Knöbl.  2004.  Sozialtheorie:  zwanzig  einführende  Vorlesungen.  Frankfurt:   Suhrkamp.  

certain   sense,   I   do   not   really   believe   in   the   possibility   of   drawing   totally   clear-­‐cut   boundaries  between  disciplines.  I  do  not  think  that  the  world  is  by  itself  structured   according   to   the   system   of   scientific   disciplines,   but   that   we   have   a   kind   of   negotiation   process   here.   I   think   the   interesting   things   are   unsolved   intellectual   problems.  It  is  totally  secondary  whether  this  is  done  by  this  or  that  discipline.  For   example,   my   discipline   is   Sociology,   but   I   think   I   bring   in   a   lot   of   knowledge   from   other  disciplines  —Anthropology,  History,  Philosophy,  Psychology,  even  Theology— .  So,  it  is  a  constant  negotiation  process  of  people  claiming  the  right  to  deal  with  this   or   that   topic   within   their   discipline   or   denying   that   right   to   others.   I   think   that   would   be   a   sociological   perspective   on   the   question   of   what   the   subject   matter   of   different  disciplines  is.       P.  B.:  In  War  and  Modernity14  you  criticize  the  myths  of  progress  and  differentiation   theory,  trying  to  rescue  the  social  historicity  and  the  contingency  of  social  processes.   Similarly,   you   suggest   that   «we   should   become   accustomed   to   considering     "modernization"   simply   as   a   collective   name   that   indicates   a   series   of   historical   changes».15   If   so,   the   difference   between   modernization   and   any   other   historical   process   vanishes.   Does   it   make   sense   to   speak   of   modernity?   If   it   made   sense:   what   social  events  could  identify  this  process?     H.   J.:   Let   me   say   first,   I   always   distinguish   between   two   different   concepts   of   modernization.   The   first   one   is   a   rather   innocent   concept   of   Modernization,   something  like  technological  and  scientific  progress  and  economic  growth.  If  this  is   what   we   mean   by   Modernization,   you   are   of   course   right,   there   has   been   modernization   in   human   history   all   the   time,   at   different   rapidity   of   course.   There   can   be   long   periods   of   economic   stagnation   or   without   much   scientific   and   technological   progress,   but   on   the   other   side   there   can   be   at   least   slow   progress.     For   example,   we   could   say   there   was   a   certain   modernization   of   agricultural   technology   in   the   Middle   Ages   in   Europa.   This   is   rather   innocent   and   has   to   do   with   the   fact   that   we   use   the   adjective   “modern”:   something   is   more   modern   than   something  from  the  past  and  we  call  this  process  of  change  “modernization”.  I  have   no  problem  with  that.       The   other   way   to   use   the   word   modernization,   the   concept   Modernization,   is   to   think   it   is   the   process   of   transition   from   an   old   epoch   to   a   new   epoch   called   Modernity.  I  have  problems  with  that  for  two  reasons:  first,  when  we  say  that,  the   crucial   question   is   when   did   this   new   epoch   called   Modernity   begin.   For   example,   when   you   ask   students   this   question   in   class,   you   get   all   sorts   of   answers:   from   1453,   when   the   Turks   defeated   the   Byzantine   Empire,   to   1492,   when   Columbus                                                                                                                  

14  Joas,  Hans.  2000.  Kriege  und  Werte:  Studien  zur  Gewaltgeschichte  des  20.  Jahrhunderts.  Metternich:   Velbrück.  (English  translation:  War  and  Modernity.  Studies  in  the  History  of  Violence  in  20th  Century,   Oxford:  Polity  Press  2003.)   15   Translation   from   the   Spanish   version:   Joas,   Hans.   2005.   Guerra   y   Modernidad.   Estudios   sobre   la   Historia   de   la   Violencia   en   el   Siglo   XX.   Barcelona:   Paidós,   p.   32.   The   full   quote  is:   “Debemos   acostumbrarnos  a  la  idea  de  que  las  discrepancias  entre  ámbitos  sociales  parciales  son  algo  normal  y   que   el   concepto   de   “modernización”   tal   vez   sólo   sea   un   nombre   colectivo   para   indicar   una   serie   de   eventos  de  cambio,  cuyas  variables  resultan  posibles  y  reales”.  

discovered   America,   or   1517,   when   Martin   Luther   published   his   95   theses   for   the   Protestant   Reformation;   then,   from   all   possible   phases   in   between   the   American   Revolution,   the   French   Revolution,   the   Industrial   Revolution,   or   major   changes   in   Art   like   the   development   of   abstract   painting   in   the   early   20th   century,   or   1945,   1968  and  1989.       Now,  from  a  scientific  point  of  view,  a  concept  is  just  useless  when  it  has  so   vague  contours.  Of  course,  we  could  just  make  an  agreement  on  what  we  mean  by   Modernity   in   the   future.   For   example,   it   could   be   the   age   after   the   Industrial   Revolution   —or   something   like   that—,   and   that   may   make   sense.   I   am   not   saying   that  all  these  different  dates  are  unimportant  or  that  it  does  not  make  sense  to  speak   about   them   as   indicating   major   historical   changes.   I   am   just   saying   that   maybe   it   does  not  help  very  much  to  call  the  time  after  that  change  Modernity.       My  second  reason  to  be  very  hesitating  is  mainly  because  Modernity  sounds   as   if   there   is   a   very   close   connection,   what   I   call   a   “tight   coupling”   —as   the   organizational   sociologists   say—,   between   different   processes.   For   example,   as   if   Democratization   is   necessarily   a   part   of   Modernity.   This   has   often   been   the   claim   of   the   people   who   speak   like   that.   Now,   are   all   modern   societies   democratic?   No,   of   course,   they   are   not   all   modern   democracies,   but   they   are   modern   in   the   chronological  sense.  Now  what  do  you  do  with  that?  You  call  this  a  special  case  and   you   need   a   special   explanation   for   that.   I   say:   this   does   not   make   sense,   this   is   smuggling  a  certain  normative  meaning  into  a  chronological  concept.       P.  B.:  That  could  be  a  problem  in  the  writings  of  Ulrich  Beck…     H.   J.:   Beck   really   has   this   problem,   but   he   solves   it   by   inventing   a   term   like   Reflexive   Modernity,   making   the   claim   that   there   was   a   kind   of   first   modernity   and   now   comes   the   second   modernity.   I   do   not   buy   that   at   all.   I   think   there   was   much   reflexivity  in  this  earlier  modernity  and  that  many  things  he  says  about  this  Second   Modernity  are  exactly  the  same  things  that  the  modernization  theorists  of  the  1950s   and   1960s   said   about   Modernity.   So,   he   just   follows   the   same   logic   the   modernization  theorists  follow,  but  introduces  a  new  historical  step  here.  I  make  a   totally  different  proposal,  mainly  to  treat  the  alleged  subprocesses  of  Modernization   as   separate   processes,   to   understand   —for   example—   that   Democratization   is   a   process  and  there  is  no  inherent  logic  of  Modernity  that  helps  Democratization.  And,   of  course,  since  one  of  my  main  areas  is  the  Sociology  of  Religion,  I  am  particularly   competent   in   elaborating   on   that   point   with   regard   to   Secularization.   Many   modernization   theorists   have   always   assumed   that   Secularization   is   a   necessary   part  of  modernization.  I  think  that  is  empirically  not  true,  from  the  United  States  to   South   Korea,   which   are   very   modern   societies   that   are   not   very   secularized.   It   is   more  fruitful  to  analyze  the  dynamic  of  Secularization,  for  example,  or  to  analyze  the   dynamic   of   Democratization,   without   such   a   unitary   notion   of   Modernity   that   ties   these  things  together  into  a  kind  of  integrated  whole.     P.  B.:  You  touch  the  issue  of  contingency  in  social  processes,  and  the  ways  of  reducing   it,   which   suppose   a   "tight   coupling"   of   the   different   dimensions   of   change   in   the   Modernization  theory.  In  my  view,  Niklas  Luhmann  is  one  of  those  sociologists  who  has  

put   great   emphasis   on   contingency.   This   is   shown,   for   example,   when   he   points   the   "improbabilities   of   communication"   or   when   he   states   the   existence   of   "functional   equivalents"  (opening  functionalism  to  a  historically  variable  content).  However,  you   have   criticized   the   theory   of   functional   differentiation   in   general   and   specifically   Luhmann   for   not   fully   accepting   contingency.   Could   you   explain   this   problem   that   you   see  in  Niklas  Luhmann's  theory?     H.   J.:   Luhmann   puts   strong   emphasis   on   Contingency,   stronger   even   than   Parsons.   We   should   not   forget   that   Parsons   already   had   emphasized   the   role   of   what   he   called  Double  Contingency  in  human  interaction  very  much,  but  Luhmann  made  this   stronger  and  stronger.  That  is  a  great  achievement,  but  my  point  is  to  say  that  the   ironic   thing   about   Luhmann   is   that   he   can   see   every   social   phenomenon   as   contingent,   with   one   exception,   which   is   the   process   of   functional   differentiation   itself.  For  him,  the  process  of  functional  differentiation  is  not  contingent.  This  is  the   one   guiding   thread   of   his   theory,   whereas   in   my   theory,   I   say   that   there   is   not   a   necessary   process   of   functional   differentiation,   because   functional   differentiation   itself  depends  on  very  specific  presuppositions.  There  are  social  conflicts  about  the   degree  and  the  specific  character  of  differentiation.  And,  it  is  simply  not  true  that  by   emphasizing   functional   differentiation   we   have   identified   the   one   master   trend   of   history.   And   again,   if   I   refer   to   my   two   empirical   research   areas,   Religion   and   War,   I   think   both   cases   are   very   clear   in   this   regard:   Religion   leads   to   innovations   that   cannot   simply   be   subsumed   under   the   logic   of   functional   differentiation   and   the   same  is  true  for  wars.  One  of  my  favorite  examples  is  the  origin  of  Italian  Fascism  in   the   experience   of   the   First   World   War.   It   just   does   not   make   sense   to   describe   Fascism   as   the   result   of   an   ongoing   process   of   functional   differentiation.   It   was   a   process  of  dealing  with  something  that  happened  in  the  War,  you  may  say  the  War   was  the  result  of  certain  processes  of  differentiation,  but  in  itself  it  was  something   totally  different,  which  had  its  own  effects  on  human  action.       P.  B.:  It  is  my  understanding  that  your  emphasis  on  contingency  has  led  you  to  use  a   genealogical   approach.   Both   in   your   article   on   universalism16   as   in   the   book   The   sacredness   of   the   person,17   you   try   to   create   an   alternative   to   approaches   based   on   Nietzsche   and   Kant   for   the   study   of   values.   With   a   similar   interest,   you   propose   the   analysis  of  the  war  an  alternative  between  Realpolitik  and  pacifist  utopia.  What  is  the   "affirmative   genealogy"?   How   can   we   link   philosophy   and   history   in   the   sociological   study  of  values?     H.  J.:  Let  me  explain  both  elements  of  this  expression.  Genealogy  is  a  term  that  was   invented  in  its  philosophical  sense  by  Nietzsche  and  was  then  very  famously  used  by   Michael   Foucault.   And,   in   both   cases   —that   is   a   good   thing—   they   speak   about   Genealogy   because   they   want   to   do   justice   to   the   contingency   of   human   history.                                                                                                                   16   Joas,   Hans.   2008.   “The   emergence   of   Universalism:   an   affirmative   Genealogy”.   Frontiers   of   sociology.   17   Joas,   Hans.   2011.   Die   sakralität   der   Person:   eine   neue   Genealogie   der   Menschenrechte.   Frankfurt:   Suhrkamp.  (English  translation  forthcoming:  Washington,  D.C.:  Georgetown  University  Press.)  

They  want  to  reconstruct  historical  processes,  but  in  a  spirit  that  shows  that  these   processes,   in   a   certain   sense,   were   not   necessary:   that   they   happened,   but   that   something   else   could   have   also   happened.   That   is   this   perspective   of   Contingency.   There  is  always  a  certain  inclination  in  people  to  see  the  things  that  happened  as  if   they  were  the  only  things  that  could  have  happened,  but  that  is  not  true.  Sometimes,   in   a   war,   it   is   very   open   who   will   gain   the   upper-­‐hand,   who   will   win.   And   then,   a   lot   depends   on   whether   the   Greeks   or   the   Persians   win   in   Salamis,   or   whether   Hitler   wins  the  Second  World  War  or  not;  a  lot  depends  on  that.  So,  I  like  the  genealogical   approach  because  of  its  ability  to  reconstruct  history  as  contingent.       But,  in  Nietzsche  and  Foucault  the  idea  was  that  when  we  do  a  genealogical   study  of  values,  this  kind  of  study  liberates  us  from  these  values.  That  is  a  positive   way   to   put   it;   the   negative   way   to   put   it   would   be   that   it   destroys   our   naive   commitment  to  these  values.  Nietzsche  clearly  assumed  that  by  showing  how  —as   he  says—  the  Jewish  value  of  Justice  or  the  Christian  value  of  Love  have  come  into   being,  we  would  lose  somehow  our  commitment  to  the  values  of  Justice  and  Love.  In   his  perspective,  this  would  be  a  good  thing,  because  it  would  make  us  more  tolerant.   Now,  I  am  saying  that  that  is  not  true.  I  can  be  fully  aware  of  the  contingency  of  the   emergence   of   my   values,   but   this   awareness   does   not   destroy   my   commitment   to   them.     I   as   a   postwar   German   can   be   fully   aware   that,   for   example,   my   interest   in   Human  Rights  has  something  to  do  with  the  German  past,  with  the  Nazi  crimes.  In   that  sense  my  interest  in  Human  Rights  is  contingent;  had  there  not  been  the  Nazi   crimes,   maybe   I   would   be   a   totally   different   human   being,   with   different   interests.   But  this  insight  does  not  weaken  my  commitment  to  Human  Rights,  not  at  all,  it  even   strengthens   it   to   some   extent.   I   say:   “Well,   these   Nazi   crimes   happened,   it   was   contingent   that   they   happened”.   If   the   Nazis   had   never   seized   power   in   Germany,   they  would  not  have  been  able  to  commit  their  crimes.  So,  all  this  is  contingent,  but   my  insight  into  that  contingency  might  even  strengthen  my  commitment  to  certain   values.  This  is  what  I  call  affirmative,  therefore,  as  the  counter  notion  to  destructive.   I  try  to  write  human  history  in  a  way  that  there  is  full  justice  to  the  contingency  of   that   history,   but,   at   the   same   time,   I   try   to   strengthen   the   commitment   to   universalist  values.  That  is  what  I  call  affirmative  genealogy  and  the  book  on  Human   Rights   is   an   attempt   to   practice   this   approach.   And,   it   also   contains   a   50   page   methodological  chapter  on  which  I  explain  how  such  a  method  could  work.     P.   B.:   In   your   genealogy   of   Human   Rights   you   propose   as   an   alternative   to   the   "Enlightenment   myth"   and   Foucault's   disciplinary   narrative,   a   focus   on   the   sacredness   of   the   person   (in   other   writing,   you   have   shown   that   it   is   also   an   alternative   to   the   "charisma  of  reason"  proposed  by  Weber).18  Why  are  both  alternatives  inadequate  and   what  are  the  benefits  of  your  proposal?     H.  J.:  The  question  you  are  posing  refers  to  one  of  six  chapters  of  the  Human  Rights   book:  chapter  two,  where  the  empirical  problem  is  how  do  we  explain  the  abolition                                                                                                                  

18   Joas,   Hans.   2002.   Creatividad,   acción   y   valores.   Hacia   una   teoría   de   la   contingencia.   México   D.   F.:   Biblioteca  de  Signos,  chapter  IV:  “El  carisma  de  los  derechos  humanos”.  

of  torture  in  Europe  in  the  18th  Century.  In  the  book  on  Human  Rights,  I  deal  with   four   empirical   cases:   the   late   18th   century   declarations   of   Human   Rights,   the   1948   Universal  Declaration  of  Human  Rights,  the  abolition  of  torture  and  the  abolition  of   slavery   and   this   particular   chapter   deals   with  the   abolition   of   torture.   I   analyze   why   in   the   year   1700   all   European   states   had   torture   as   part   of   their   punitive   justice   system  and  in  the  year  1800  none  of  them  had  it.  Something  must  have  happened   between  1700  and  1800.  What  was  that  and  why  did  it  happen?       In   the   literature   you   have   two   dominant   interpretations.     One   is   that   it   was   the   initiative   of   certain   courageous   enlightened   male   intellectuals   to   abolish   torture   and   there   are   different   candidates   for   that   role:   one   is   the   Italian   intellectual   Cesare   Beccaria  and  another  one  is  the  Prussian  King  Frederick  II,  who  in  1740  made  also   some   steps   to   abolish   torture.   I   try   to   empirically   show   why   both   descriptions   are   not  correct.  I  say  that  the  process  of  the  abolition  of  torture  in  Europe  had  already   set   in,   had   already   begun   before   Beccaria   published   his   book.   Actually,   he   even   refers  to  those  cases  in  his  book,  so  he  cannot  be  the  lonely  innovator  here.    And  also   —I  do  not  want  to  get  into  all  these  details  now,  because  you  can  find  them  in  the   book—  Frederick  II's  initiative  was  much  less  courageous  and  not  as  crucial  as  some   people  have  been  tempted  to  assume.  So,  this  is  one  of  the  conventional  descriptions   and  it  is  clearly  empirically  not  correct.       The  other  one  is  this  Foucauldian  description,  where  actors  do  not  play  a  role   at  all  and  where  the  abolition  of  torture  is  not  even  described  as  a  kind  of  progress,   it  is  just  a  switch  in  the  organization  of  power.  This  is  something  that  I  find  already   from  the  outset  not  very  appealing,  but  I  try  to  show  why  what  Foucault  describes  in   several  of  his  books  with  regard  to  the  18th   century  as  a  process  of  exclusion  is  in   fact  more  a  process  of  inclusion,  in  the  sense  that  more  human  beings  were  seen  as   fully  human  beings.  This  has  something  to  do  with  the  formation  of  the  asylum,  for   example:  it  may  look  as  an  exclusion  and  it  is  a  physical  exclusion,  but  it  is  a  logical   inclusion,   because   you   treat   human   beings   as   curable,   as   people   who   can   act   differently.       And,   with   regard   to   torture,   I   try   to   show   that   the   true   cultural   transformation  here  is  what  I  call  “sacralization  of  the  person”,  namely  an  increased   sensitivity   with   regard   to   the   fact   that   even   the   most   brutish   criminal   remains   a   human  being,  and  that  even  if  we  find  his  crimes  horrible,  it  does  not  imply  that  we   can   treat   the   criminal   as   horribly   as   the   criminal   treated   his   victims.   So   I   say   that   this  sacralization  dynamic  sets  in  and  leads  to  a  sensitization  of  the  population  and   of  lawgivers  with  regard  to  the  brutal  nature  of  punishment.       P.   B.:   You   share   with   some   authors   (like   Castoriadis,   Giddens,   Bourdieu   and   Sennett,   maybe  Touraine  and  Etzioni)  a  critique  of  the  philosophy  of  consciousness  and  of  the   teleological   action   theory,   which   leads   them   to   raise   an   alternative   base   of   action   to   overcome   dichotomies   such   as   individual/society,   culture/materiality,   agency/structure,   rationality/normativity.   You   and   these   authors   also   point   out   an   important   opening   to   historicity.   Do   you   think   that   this   is   a   new   paradigm   of   social   science?    

H.   J.:   I   would   have   to   speak   about   these   authors   individually.   I   knew   Cornelius   Castoriadis   very   well,   I   mean   also   personally,   and   I   am   certainly   very   much   influenced   by   Castoriadis'   philosophy   of   creativity,   but   I   am   not   influenced   very   much   by   his   politics.   I   would   like   to   add   that,   because   there   are   some   people   who   mostly  love  his  politics,  I  do  not  love  his  politics  so  much,  but  I  love  his  philosophy.   On   the   other   hand,   Castoriadis'   philosophy   was   very   far   from   being   professional   social   science,   so   I   could   get   some   philosophical   inspiration   from   him,   but   not   the   elaboration  of  a  theory  of  creativity  of  the  action.  Giddens  was  important  for  me  in   the  1980s,  both  with  regard  to  the  understanding  of  action  and  with  regard  to  the   nation-­‐state   and   violence,   as   one   of   his   books   was   titled.19   But,   I   think   Giddens   after   about   1990,   more   or   less,   lost   interest   in   sociological   theorizing.   His   later   publications  are  either  on  the    journalistic  level  or  this  political  advisory  genre  and   not   very   systematic   theory.   About   Bourdieu:   I   see   him   as   very   different,   as   I   have   said  before.  And  Sennett,  interestingly  had  a  kind  of  change  in  his  orientation,  in  the   direction   of   pragmatism,   in   the   last   ten   years   or   so   has   began   calling   himself   pragmatist.   You   mentioned   Touraine   and   Etzioni,   they   should   be   definitely   on   the   list.       Now  perhaps,  in  concluding,  you  ask  if  this  is  a  new  paradigm  or  not.  Since  I   believe   that   so   much   in   this   paradigm   has   old   historical   roots   in   Pragmatism,   Historicism  and  Hermeneutics,  I  am  hesitating  to  call  it  new.  But,  I  think  that  there   are   contemporary   attempts   to   continue   a   tradition   that   certainly   goes   back   to   the   19th,   if   not   the   18th   century,   and   that   if   we   see   the   commonalities   of   these   authors   and   we   see   the   systematic   quality   of   that   approach   —creativity   of   action,   contingency   of   social   change—,   then   we   see   that   there   is   indeed   a   very   serious   competitor   to   these   economic   rational   models   that   are   so   influential   in   the   contemporary  world  and  to  the  Kantian-­‐Habermasian  models.  So,  yes,  in  that  sense  I   would  say  yes.     P.B.:   Thank   you   very   much,   Professor   Joas,   for   receiving   me   so   kindly   and   sharing   your   ideas  with  me.    

                                                                                                               

19   Giddens,   Anthony.   1985.   A   Contemporary   Critique   of   Historical   Materialism.   (Vol.   II:   The   Nation-­‐ State  and  Violence).  Cambridge:  Polity.