STRUCTURE AND PROPERTIES OF LARGE

0 downloads 0 Views 568KB Size Report
intersecting family, in which no element is contained in more than a -proportion of the ..... For shorthand, we say that ҄³ is minimal w.r.t. common intersection.
STRUCTURE AND PROPERTIES OF LARGE INTERSECTING FAMILIES ANDREY KUPAVSKII

Abstract. We say that a family of π‘˜-subsets of an 𝑛-element set is intersecting, if any two of its sets intersect. In this paper we study properties and structure of large intersecting families. We prove a conclusive version of Frankl’s theorem on intersecting families with bounded maximal degree. This theorem, along with its generalizations to cross-intersecting families, strengthens the results obtained by Frankl, Frankl and Tokushige, Kupavskii and Zakharov and others. We study the structure of large intersecting families, obtaining some very general structural theorems which extend the results of Han and Kohayakawa, as well as Kostochka and Mubayi. We also obtain an extension of some classic problems on intersecting families introduced in the 70s. We extend an old result of Frankl, in which he determined the size and structure of the largest intersecting family of π‘˜-sets with covering number 3 for 𝑛 > 𝑛0 (π‘˜). We obtain the same result for 𝑛 > πΆπ‘˜, where 𝐢 is an absolute constant. Finally, we obtain a similar extension for the following problem of Erd˝os, Rothschild and SzΒ΄emeredi: what is the largest intersecting family, in which no element is contained in more than a 𝑐-proportion of the sets, for different values of 𝑐.

1. Introduction For integers π‘Ž ≀ 𝑏, put [π‘Ž, 𝑏] := {π‘Ž, π‘Ž + 1, . . . , 𝑏}, and denote [𝑛] := [1,(︀𝑛])οΈ€for shorthand. For a set 𝑋, denote by 2𝑋 its power set and, for integer π‘˜ β‰₯ 0, denote by π‘‹π‘˜ the collection of all π‘˜-element subsets (π‘˜-sets) of 𝑋. A family is simply a collection of sets. We call a family intersecting, if any two of its sets intersect. A β€œtrivial” example of an intersecting family is the family of all sets containing a fixed element. We call a family non-trivial, if the intersection of all sets from the family is empty. One of the oldest and most famous results in extremal combinatorics is the Erd˝os–Ko–Rado theorem: (οΈ€[𝑛])οΈ€ Theorem 1.1 ([11]). Let 𝑛 β‰₯ 2π‘˜ > 0 and consider an intersecting family β„± βŠ‚ . Then π‘˜ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’1)οΈ€ |β„±| ≀ π‘˜βˆ’1 . Moreover, for 𝑛 > 2π‘˜ the equality holds only for the families of all π‘˜-sets containing a given element. Answering a question of Erd˝os, Ko, and Rado, Hilton and Milner [33] found the size and structure of the largest non-trivial intersecting families of π‘˜-sets. For π‘˜ β‰₯ 4, up to a permutation of the ground set, it must have the form β„‹π‘˜ , where for integer 2 ≀ 𝑒 ≀ π‘˜ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {︁ }︁ {︁ }︁ [𝑛] [𝑛] (1.1) ℋ𝑒 := 𝐴 ∈ : [2, 𝑒 + 1] βŠ‚ 𝐴 βˆͺ 𝐴 ∈ : 1 ∈ 𝐴, [2, 𝑒 + 1] ∩ 𝐴 ΜΈ= βˆ… . π‘˜ π‘˜ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’1)οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1)οΈ€ (οΈ€ )οΈ€ π’₯1 has size π‘˜βˆ’1 βˆ’ π‘˜βˆ’1 + 1, which is much smaller than π‘›βˆ’1 , provided 𝑛 is large as π‘˜βˆ’1 compared to π‘˜. For a family β„± βŠ‚ 2[𝑛] and 𝑖 ∈ [𝑛], the degree 𝑑𝑖 (β„±) of 𝑖 in β„± is the number of sets from β„± containing 𝑖. Let βˆ†(β„±) stand for the maximal degree of an element in β„±. Frankl [16] proved the following far-reaching generalization of the Hilton–Milner theorem. The research was supported by the Advanced Postdoc.Mobility grant no. P300P2 177839 of the Swiss National Science Foundation. 1

(οΈ€[𝑛])οΈ€ Theorem 1.2 ([16]). Let 𝑛 > 2π‘˜ > 0 and β„± βŠ‚ be an intersecting family. If βˆ†(β„±) ≀ π‘˜ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’1)οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1)οΈ€ βˆ’ π‘˜βˆ’1 for some integer 3 ≀ 𝑒 ≀ π‘˜, then π‘˜βˆ’1 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘›βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1 |β„±| ≀ + βˆ’ . π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘˜βˆ’1 One can deduce the Hilton–Milner theorem from the 𝑒 = π‘˜ case of Theorem 1.2. Theorem 1.2 is sharp for integer values of 𝑒, as witnessed by the example (1.1). On a high level, it provides us with an upper bound on |β„±| in terms of the size of the largest trivial subfamily (star) in β„±. Let us state a stronger version of Theorem 1.2 in dual terms. For a family β„±, the diversity 𝛾(β„±) is the quantity |β„±| βˆ’ βˆ†(β„±). One may think of diversity as of the distance from β„± to the closest star. The following strengthening of Theorem 1.2 was obtained by Kupavskii and Zakharov [43]. (οΈ€[𝑛])οΈ€ Theorem 1.3 ([43]). Let 𝑛 > 2π‘˜ > 0 and β„± βŠ‚ be an intersecting family. If 𝛾(β„±) β‰₯ π‘˜ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1)οΈ€ for some real 3 ≀ 𝑒 ≀ π‘˜, then π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘›βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1 (1.2) |β„±| ≀ + βˆ’ . π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘˜βˆ’1 We note that the Hilton–Milner theorem, as well as Theorem 1.2, is immediately implied by Theorem 1.3. The deduction of Theorem 1.3 from Theorem 1.2 for integer values of 𝑒 is possible, but not straightforward. Theorem 1.3 provides the strongest known stability result for the Erd˝os–Ko–Rado for large intersecting families, more precisely, for the families (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€theorem )οΈ€ π‘›βˆ’3 of size at least π‘›βˆ’2 +2 . There are several other stability results for the Erd˝os–Ko–Rado π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 theorem, see, e.g. [6, 9, 28]. In Section 2, we prove a conclusive version of Theorem 1.3, which gives the precise dependence of size of an intersecting family β„± of π‘˜-sets on (the lower bound on) 𝛾(β„±). The result then is extended to cover the equality case, as well as the weighted case and the case of cross-intersecting families. In particular, it strengthens the results of [16], [25], [43]. One of the main ingredients in the proof of the main result of Section 2 (as well as in the proofs of Theorems 1.2, 1.3) is the famous Kruskal–Katona theorem [40, 37]. This theorem is a central result in extremal set theory and has numerous applications (see, e.g., [2, 4]). Another key ingredient is the bipartite switching trick, which was introduced in [43] (similar ideas appeared earlier in [21]). In this paper, we exploit this trick to a much greater extent. We do not state the aforementioned theorem in this section since it requires some preparations. Instead, we state the following corollary, which can be seen as a generalization of the Hilton–Milner phenomena. (οΈ€[𝑛])οΈ€ Corollary 1.4. Let 𝑛 > 2π‘˜ β‰₯ 8 and β„± βŠ‚ be an intersecting family. Suppose that π‘˜ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1)οΈ€ 𝛾(β„±) > π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 for some integer 4 ≀ 𝑒 ≀ π‘˜. Then (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘›βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 (1.3) |β„±| ≀ + βˆ’ βˆ’ + 1. π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘˜βˆ’2 (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€ )οΈ€ βˆ’ Moreover, the same inequality holds for 𝑛 > 2π‘˜ β‰₯ 6 with 𝑒 = 3 if π‘›βˆ’4 < 𝛾(β„±) ≀ π‘›βˆ’3 π‘˜βˆ’3 π‘˜βˆ’2 (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2)οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’3)οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’3)οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’4)οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2)οΈ€ + 1 or π‘˜βˆ’2 < 𝛾(β„±) ≀ π‘˜βˆ’2 + π‘˜βˆ’2 βˆ’ π‘˜βˆ’2 + 1. π‘˜βˆ’2 (οΈ€ )οΈ€ Compare (1.3) with (1.2) for integer 𝑒. The difference in the bounds is π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 βˆ’ 1, while π‘˜βˆ’2 the lower bounds on diversity differ by 1. Thus, Corollary 1.4 states that the (οΈ€size of)οΈ€ the largest family with diversity at least 𝛾 has a big drop when 𝛾 passes the point π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1 for π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 integer 𝑒. We also note that Corollary 1.4 is sharp, as it will be clear from Section 2.

in

Numerous authors aimed to determine precisely, what are the largest intersecting families (οΈ€[𝑛])οΈ€ with certain restrictions. One of such questions was studied by Han and Kohayakawa, π‘˜

who determined the largest family of intersecting families that is neither contained in the Erd˝os–Ko–Rado family, nor in the Hilton–Milner family. In our terms, the question can be simply restated as follows: what is the largest intersecting family with 𝛾(β„±) β‰₯ 2? The proof of Han and Kohayakawa is quite technical and long. Kruskal–Katona-based arguments allow for a very short and simple proof in the case π‘˜ β‰₯ 5. For 𝑖 ∈ [π‘˜] let us put 𝐼𝑖 := [𝑖 + 1, π‘˜ + 𝑖] and (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {︁ }︁ [𝑛] π’₯𝑖 := {𝐼1 , 𝐼𝑖 } βˆͺ 𝐹 ∈ : 1 ∈ 𝐹, 𝐹 ∩ 𝐼1 ΜΈ= βˆ…, 𝐹 ∩ 𝐼𝑖 ΜΈ= βˆ… . π‘˜ (οΈ€[𝑛])οΈ€ We note that π’₯𝑖 βŠ‚ π‘˜ and that π’₯𝑖 is intersecting for every 𝑖 ∈ [π‘˜]. Moreover, 𝛾(π’₯𝑖 ) = 2 for 𝑖 > 1 and π’₯1 is the Hilton–Milner family. It is an easy calculation to see that |π’₯𝑖 | > |π’₯𝑖+1 | for every π‘˜ β‰₯ 4 and 𝑖 ∈ [π‘˜ βˆ’ 1].1 Theorem 1.5 ([31]). Let 𝑛 > 2π‘˜, π‘˜ β‰₯ 4. Then any intersecting family β„± with 𝛾(β„±) β‰₯ 2 satisfies (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘›βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 (1.4) |β„±| ≀ βˆ’ βˆ’ + 2, π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘˜βˆ’2 moreover, for π‘˜ β‰₯ 5 the equality is attained only on the families isomorphic to π’₯2 . We note that Han and Kohayakawa also proved their theorem for π‘˜ = 3, as well as described the cases of equality for π‘˜ = 4. These cases are more tedious and do not follow from our methods in a straightforward way. However, Theorem 1.5 can be deduced without much effort. A slightly weaker version of the theorem above (without uniqueness) is a consequence of the main result in the paper by Hilton and Milner [33] (cf. also [31]). Applying Corollary 1.4 with 𝑒 = π‘˜, we conclude that (1.4) holds for π‘˜ β‰₯ 4. The bound is sharp, as witnessed by π’₯2 . The uniqueness requires hardly more effort, but since it uses Theorem 2.3, stated in Section 2, we postpone its proof until Section 3. For any set 𝑋, family β„± βŠ‚ 2𝑋 and 𝑖 ∈ 𝑋, we use the following standard notations β„±(¯𝑖) := {𝐹 : 𝑖 ∈ / 𝐹 ∈ β„±} and β„±(𝑖) := {𝐹 βˆ– {𝑖} : 𝑖 ∈ 𝐹 ∈ β„±}. (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€ )οΈ€ Note that β„±(¯𝑖) βŠ‚ π‘‹βˆ–{𝑖} and β„±(𝑖) βŠ‚ π‘‹βˆ–{𝑖} . π‘˜ π‘˜βˆ’1 β‹‚οΈ€ Denote by ℰ𝑙 the maximal intersecting family with |ℰ𝑙 (Β―1)| = 𝑙, | πΈβˆˆβ„°π‘™ (Β―1) 𝐸| = π‘˜ βˆ’ 1 (note that the family is defined up to isomorphism). Note that π’₯2 is isomorphic to β„°2 .2 It is not difficult to see that for π‘˜ βˆ’ 1 < 𝑙 < 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜ we have ℰ𝑙 βŠ‚ β„°π‘›βˆ’π‘˜ : we have ℰ𝑙 (1) = β„°π‘›βˆ’π‘˜ (1) for this range. The following theorem is one of the main results in [39]: (οΈ€ )οΈ€ Theorem 1.6 ([39]). Let π‘˜ β‰₯ 5 and 𝑛 = 𝑛(π‘˜) be sufficiently large. If β„± βŠ‚ [𝑛] is intersecting π‘˜ and |β„±| > |π’₯3 | then β„± βŠ‚ ℰ𝑙 for 𝑙 ∈ {0, . . . π‘˜ βˆ’ 1, 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜}. We note that it is easy to verify that |π’₯3 | < |β„°π‘›βˆ’π‘˜ |, e.g., for 𝑛 > 4π‘˜. The authors of [39] we using the delta-systems method of Frankl.3 Actually, Theorem 1.6 can be deduced from the results of Frankl [14] with little extra effort. Many results in extremal set theory are much easier to obtain once one assumes that 𝑛 is sufficiently large in comparison to π‘˜. (The possibility to apply the delta-method is one of the reasons.) In particular, the bound on 𝑛 in Theorem 1.6 is doubly exponential in π‘˜. In this 1Indeed,

the difference |π’₯𝑖 | βˆ’ |π’₯𝑖+1 | is

(οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2)οΈ€

βˆ’ 1 for 𝑖 = 1 and

(οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’π‘–)οΈ€

βˆ’

(οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’π‘–βˆ’1)οΈ€

π‘˜βˆ’1

π‘˜βˆ’1

=

(οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’π‘–βˆ’1)οΈ€

for π‘˜βˆ’2 𝑖 β‰₯ 2. 2Cf. the discussion in the beginning of Section 2.1 and note the relation to the lexicographic families, defined in Section 2: ℰ𝑙 (Β― 1) is isomorphic to β„’([2, 𝑛], 𝑙, π‘˜). Using Theorems 2.4 and 2.9 (or by tedious direct calculation), we can conclude that |β„°π‘˜βˆ’1 | < |β„°π‘˜βˆ’2 | = |β„°π‘›βˆ’π‘˜ | < |β„°π‘˜βˆ’3 | < . . . < |β„°1 |. 3The goal of their paper, was, in a sense, to draw the attention of the researchers to this method. π‘˜βˆ’2

paper, we deduce Theorem 1.6 from a much more general result, which, additionally, holds without any restriction on 𝑛. A family is called minimal with respect to some property, if none of its proper subfamilies possesses the property. For shorthand, we say that β‹‚οΈ€ β„³ is minimal w.r.t. common intersection β‹‚οΈ€ if, for any 𝑀𝑙 ∈ β„³, we have | 𝑀 βˆˆβ„³βˆ–{𝑀𝑙 } 𝑀 | > | 𝑀 βˆˆβ„³ 𝑀 |. The following theorem is one of the main results of this paper. (οΈ€ )οΈ€ Theorem 1.7. Assume that 𝑛 > 2π‘˜ β‰₯ 8. Consider an intersecting family β„± βŠ‚ [𝑛] with π‘˜ βˆ†(β„±) = 𝑑1 (β„±). β‹‚οΈ€Take a subfamily β„³ βŠ‚ β„±(Β―1), which is minimal w.r.t. common intersection and such that | 𝑀 βˆˆβ„³ 𝑀 | = 𝑑. Take the (unique) maximal intersecting family β„± β€² , such that β„± β€² (Β―1) = β„³. If 𝑑 β‰₯ 3 then we have |β„±| ≀ |β„± β€² |,

(1.5)

and, for π‘˜ β‰₯ 5 equality is possible ifβ‹‚οΈ€and only if β„± is isomorphic to β„± β€² . Moreover, if β„± is as above and | 𝐹 βˆˆβ„± (Β―1) 𝐹 | ≀ 𝑑 for some 𝑑 β‰₯ 3, then |β„±| ≀ |π’₯π‘˜βˆ’π‘‘+1 |,

(1.6)

and, for π‘˜ β‰₯ 5, equality is possible only if β„± is isomorphic to π’₯π‘˜βˆ’π‘‘+1 . This theorem generalizes Theorems 1.5 and 1.6 and gives a reasonable classification of all large intersecting families. We also note that we cannot in general replace the condition on 𝑑 by 𝑑 β‰₯ 2. Indeed, one can see that the family β„‹2 (cf. (1.1)) is much larger than π’₯π‘˜βˆ’1 for large 𝑛.4 Corollary 1.8. The statement of Theorem 1.6 is valid for any 𝑛 > 2π‘˜ β‰₯ 10. Proof of Corollary β‹‚οΈ€ 1.8. Fix any β„± as in Theorem 1.8 and assume that βˆ†(β„±) = 𝑑1 (β„±). First assume that | 𝐹 βˆˆβ„± (Β―1) | ≀ π‘˜ βˆ’ 2. Since π‘˜ β‰₯ 5, we are in position to apply the second part of β‹‚οΈ€ Theorem 1.7 to β„±, and get a contradiction with |β„±| > |π’₯3 |. Therefore, | 𝐹 βˆˆβ„± (Β―1) 𝐹 | = π‘˜ βˆ’ 1 and thus β„±(Β―1) is isomorphic to ℰ𝑙 (Β―1) for 𝑙 = |β„±(Β―1)|, which concludes the proof.  The proof of Theorem 1.7 is given in Section 3.1. The main tool of the proof of Theorem 1.7 is again the aforementioned bipartite switching trick. In this paper, we exploit it to much greater extent than in [21] and [43]. One key observation that allows us to prove Theorem 1.7 is that this bipartite switching is possible even in situations when we know practically nothing about the structure of the family. In the remaining part of the introduction, we present two results that extend some classic results of Frankl, Erd˝os Rothshild and Semeredi, and Furedi proven for 𝑛 > 𝑛0 (π‘˜) (with double-exponential dependency on π‘˜, coming from the aforementioned delta-method) to the range 𝑛 > πΆπ‘˜, where 𝐢 is an absolute constant. Apart from the bipartite switching trick, we use as a main tool the junta approximation theorem due to Dinur and Friedgut [8]. The approach is resemblant of the recent paper [41] of the author, but here we apply it to a much wider class of problems. The rough framework of combining junta method to get approximate structure with combinatorial arguments for finer structure was used in an excellent recent paper [38]. One novel aspect in the use of junta method in the first problem below is that the actual extremal configuration is quite far from being a junta (i.e., the family is not defined by the intersection with a constant-size subset of the ground set, see precise definition in Section 4)! This, of course, poses additional complications. For a family β„±, let 𝜏 (β„±) denote the covering number of β„±, that is, the minimum size of set 𝑆 that intersects all sets in β„±. Each such 𝑆 we call a hitting set. 4The

size of π’₯π‘˜βˆ’1 can be bounded by 𝑛 > 2π‘˜ 2 , say.

(οΈ€π‘›βˆ’2)οΈ€ π‘˜βˆ’2

+

(οΈ€π‘›βˆ’3)οΈ€ π‘˜βˆ’2

+ 2 + (π‘˜ βˆ’ 2)

(οΈ€(οΈ€π‘›βˆ’4)οΈ€ π‘˜βˆ’2

βˆ’

(οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2)οΈ€)οΈ€ π‘˜βˆ’2


πΆπ‘˜, where 𝐢 is an absolute constant, independent of π‘˜. An important tool in the proof (as well as in the proof of Theorem 2.4) is Lemma 3.1, in which we found an elegant way to bound the sizes of families β„± satisfying 𝜏 (β„±) = 3 and 𝜏 (β„±(Β―1)) = 2, and where β„±(Β―1) is minimal w.r.t. this property. In the paper [23], the authors managed to extend the result of [14] to the case 𝜏 = 4, determining the exact value of 𝑐(𝑛, π‘˜, 4) and the structure of the extremal family for 𝑛 > 𝑛0 (π‘˜). The analysis in [23] is much more complicated than that in [14], and the problem for 𝜏 β‰₯ 5 is still wide open. The result of [23] may be extended to much smaller 𝑛 in a similar way, but, of course, progress on the case 𝜏 β‰₯ 5 would be more interesting. Erd˝os, Rothschild and SzemerΒ΄ (οΈ€[𝑛])οΈ€edi (cf. [10]) raised the following question: how large can the intersecting family β„± βŠ‚ π‘˜ be, given that βˆ†(β„±) ≀ 𝑐|β„±|. They proved that, for any fixed 2/3 < 𝑐 < 1, there exists 𝑛0 (π‘˜, 𝑐), such that for any 𝑛 > 𝑛0 (π‘˜, 𝑐) the largest intersecting family under this restriction is β„‹2 (see (1.1)), up to isomorphism. Stronger results of this type were proven by Frankl [14] and by FΒ¨ uredi [29]. See also a survey [7], where the concise statement of the results is given. The methods we developed in this paper allow us to extend these results to the range 𝑛 > πΆπ‘˜, where 𝐢 depends on 𝑐 only. We are going to illustrate it for one such theorem, but we note that the same ideas would work for other cases. Let us state one of the theorems, proven in [14]. Recall that a Fano plane (projective plane of order 2) 𝒫 is a family consisting of 7 3-element sets 𝑃1 , . . . , 𝑃7 , such that |𝑃𝑖 ∩ 𝑃𝑗 | = 1 for each 𝑖 ΜΈ= 𝑗. (οΈ€ )οΈ€ Theorem 1.11 ([14]). Suppose that β„± βŠ‚ [𝑛] is intersecting, and βˆ†(β„±) ≀ 𝑐|β„±| for some π‘˜ 𝑐 ∈ (3/7, 1/2). Assume that β„± has the largest cardinality among such families. Then, for any 𝑛 > 𝑛0 (𝑐, π‘˜), β„± is isomorphic to (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {︁ }︁ [𝑛] π’Ÿ3/7 := 𝐹 ∈ : 𝑃 βŠ‚ 𝐹 for some 𝑃 ∈ 𝒫 . π‘˜ Our contribution here is as follows.

Theorem 1.12. There exists an absolute constant 𝐢, such that the following holds. In terms of Theorem 1.11, if there exists πœ– > 0, such that 𝑐 ∈ [3/7 + πœ–, 1/2 βˆ’ πœ–], then the conclusion of Theorem 1.11 holds for 𝑛 > πΆπœ– π‘˜. The proof of this theorem is given in Section 4.2. In Section 5, we discuss our results and methods, as well as pose some open problems. 2. The complete diversity version of Frankl’s theorem Let us begin with the statement of the Kruskal–Katona theorem. We shall state the Kruskal–Katona theorem in two different forms, but the most handy for our purposes is the form due to Hilton in terms of cross-intersecting families. Let us (︀𝑋 )οΈ€first give some definitions. For a set 𝑋, lexicographical order (lex) β‰Ί on the sets from π‘˜ is a total order, in which 𝐴 β‰Ί 𝐡 iff the (οΈ€|𝑋|)οΈ€minimal element of 𝐴 βˆ– 𝐡 is smaller than the minimal element of 𝐡 βˆ– 𝐴. For 0 ≀ π‘š ≀ π‘˜ let β„’(𝑋, π‘š, π‘˜) be the collection of π‘š largest π‘˜-element subsets of 𝑋 with respect to lex. We say that two families π’œ, ℬ are cross-intersecting if 𝐴 ∩ 𝐡 ΜΈ= βˆ… for any 𝐴 ∈ π’œ, 𝐡 ∈ ℬ. (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€[𝑛])οΈ€ Theorem 2.1 ([40],[37]). If π’œ βŠ‚ [𝑛] , ℬ βŠ‚ are cross-intersecting then the families π‘Ž 𝑏 β„’([𝑛], |π’œ|, π‘Ž), β„’([𝑛], |ℬ|, 𝑏) are also cross-intersecting. In this section, we analyze in great details the relationship between the diversity of an intersecting family and its size. We first note that, if the value of diversity is given precisely, then it is easy to determine the largest intersecting family with such diversity. Indeed, the subfamilies of sets containing the element of the largest degree and not containing the element of the largest degree are cross-intersecting, and one can get exact bounds using Theorem 2.1. Studying the size of an intersecting family with given upper bounds on diversity is not interesting: the largest intersecting family has diversity 0. In this section we obtain the concluding version of Theorem 1.3, which tells exactly, how large an intersecting family may be, given a lower bound on its diversity. We determine all β€œextremal” values of diversity and the sizes of the corresponding families. The difficulty to obtain such a version of Theorem 1.3 is that, while Theorem 2.1 gives a very strong and clear characterisation of families with fixed diversity, the size of the family is not monotone w.r.t. diversity (the size of the largest family with given diversity does not necessarily decrease as diversity increases, although it is true in β€œmost” cases). Moreover, the numerical dependence between maximal possible sizes of π’œ and ℬ given by Theorem 2.1 is complicated and difficult to work with, see [22] and [27]. Thus, an effort is needed to find the right point of view on the problem. We shall give two versions of the main theorem of this section. First, we give a β€œquantitative” version with explicit sharp bounds on the size of intersecting families depending on the lower bound on their diversity. It may be more practical to apply in some cases, but it is difficult to grasp what is hidden behind the binomial coefficients in the formulation. Thus, later in the section (and as an intermediate step of the proof), we shall give a β€œconceptual” version of our main theorem. We note that the proof that we present is completely computationfree. In Sections 2.3, 2.4 we present strengthenings and generalisations of our main result. The cases of equality in Theorems 2.3 and 2.4 are described in Theorem 2.9. We provide a weighted version of the main result and a generalization to the case of cross-intersecting families. We note that the main results of the section are meaningful for any π‘˜ β‰₯ 3. (οΈ€(This )οΈ€ is by no [𝑛] means a serious restriction since possible structure of intersecting families in π‘˜ for π‘˜ ≀ 2 is trivial.) The following representation of natural numbers is important for the (classic form of) the Kruskal–Katona theorem. Given positive integers 𝛾 and π‘˜, one can always write down 𝛾

uniquely in the π‘˜-cascade form: (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘Žπ‘˜ π‘Žπ‘˜βˆ’1 π‘Žπ‘  𝛾= + + ... + , π‘Žπ‘˜ > π‘Žπ‘˜βˆ’1 > . . . > π‘Žπ‘  β‰₯ 1. π‘˜ π‘˜βˆ’1 𝑠 For the sake of comparison, let us state the classical version of the Kruskal–Katona theorem (equivalent to Theorem 2.1). (οΈ€ )οΈ€ Theorem 2.2 ([40],[37]). Let β„± βŠ‚ [𝑛] and put π‘˜ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {οΈ€ β€² }οΈ€ [𝑛] πœ•(β„±) := 𝐹 ∈ : 𝐹 β€² βŠ‚ 𝐹 for some 𝐹 ∈ β„± . π‘˜βˆ’1 (οΈ€π‘Žπ‘  )οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘Žπ‘˜ )οΈ€ If |β„±| = π‘˜ + . . . + 𝑠 , then (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘Žπ‘˜ π‘Žπ‘˜βˆ’1 π‘Žπ‘  |πœ•(β„±)| β‰₯ + + ... + . π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘ βˆ’1 Next, (οΈ€ )οΈ€we start preparations to state the main result of this section. Given a number 𝛾 < π‘›βˆ’1 , let us write it in the (𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)-cascade form: π‘˜βˆ’1 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ 𝑛 βˆ’ 𝑏1 𝑛 βˆ’ 𝑏2 𝑛 βˆ’ 𝑏𝑠 𝑏 𝛾= + + ... + , π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜ βˆ’ 𝑠𝑏 where 1 < 𝑏1 < 𝑏2 < . . . < 𝑏𝑠𝑏 .5 Define 𝑇𝛾 := {𝑏1 , . . . , 𝑏𝑠𝑏 } and put 𝑆𝛾 := 𝑇𝛾 βŠ• [2, 𝑏𝑠𝑏 βˆ’ 1], where βŠ• stands for symmetric difference. Note that 𝑆𝛾 βˆͺ 𝑇𝛾 = [2, 𝑏𝑠𝑏 ] and 𝑆𝛾 ∩ 𝑇𝛾 = {𝑏𝑠𝑏 }. Suppose that 𝑆𝛾 = {π‘Ž1 , . . . , π‘Žπ‘ π‘Ž }, where 1 < π‘Ž1 < . . . < π‘Žπ‘ π‘Ž := 𝑏𝑠𝑏 . (οΈ€ )οΈ€ Definition 1. We call a nonnegative integer 𝛾 resistant, if either 𝛾 = π‘›βˆ’4 or the following π‘˜βˆ’3 holds: (1) π‘ π‘Ž := |𝑆𝛾 | ≀ π‘˜ and 𝑠𝑏 := |𝑇𝛾 | ≀ π‘˜ βˆ’ 1; (2) 𝑏𝑖 > 2𝑖 + 2 for each 𝑖 ∈ [𝑠𝑏 ]. (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€ )οΈ€ In particular, any integer 𝛾 > π‘›βˆ’4 has π‘›βˆ’4 as one of the summands in the (𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)π‘˜βˆ’3 π‘˜βˆ’3 cascade form, and thus is not resistant. (οΈ€ )οΈ€ Let 0 = 𝛾0 < 𝛾1 < . . . < π›Ύπ‘š = π‘›βˆ’4 be all the resistant numbers in increasing order. π‘˜βˆ’3 (οΈ€ )οΈ€ Theorem 2.3. Let 𝑛 > 2π‘˜ β‰₯ 6. Consider an intersecting family β„± βŠ‚ [𝑛] . Suppose that π‘˜ π›Ύπ‘™βˆ’1 < 𝛾(β„±) ≀ 𝛾𝑙 for 𝑙 ∈ [π‘š] and that the representation of 𝛾𝑙 in the (𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)-cascade form is (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ 𝑛 βˆ’ 𝑏1 𝑛 βˆ’ 𝑏2 𝑛 βˆ’ 𝑏𝑠 𝑏 𝛾𝑙 = + + ... + , π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜ βˆ’ 𝑠𝑏 then (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘Ž1 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘Ž2 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘Žπ‘  π‘Ž + + ... + + 𝛾𝑙 , (2.1) |β„±| ≀ π‘›βˆ’π‘˜ π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜ βˆ’ π‘ π‘Ž + 1 where {𝑏1 , . . . , 𝑏𝑠𝑏 } = 𝑇𝛾𝑙 and {π‘Ž1 , . . . , π‘Žπ‘ π‘Ž } = 𝑆𝛾𝑙 . The expression in the right hand side of (2.1) strictly decreases as 𝑙 increases. Moreover, the presented bound is sharp: for each 𝑙 = 1, . . . , π‘š there exists an intersecting family with diversity 𝛾𝑙 which achieves the bound in (2.1). Theorem 1.3 and the concept of diversity was successfully used to advance in several problems concerning intersecting families [13, 20, 36, 42]. However, sometimes the statement of Theorem 1.3 was not fine-grained enough for the applications, and some extra work was needed to deduce some rudimentary versions of Theorem 2.3. (One example of an application of an easy application of Theorem 2.3 is Theorem 1.5 in the introduction.) This is one of our motivations for proving Theorem 2.3. The other motivation is the desire to have the 5Note

that if 𝑏1 = 1 then 𝛾 β‰₯

(οΈ€π‘›βˆ’1)οΈ€ π‘˜

β‰₯

(οΈ€π‘›βˆ’1)οΈ€ π‘˜βˆ’1

, which contradicts our assumption on 𝛾.

conclusive version of Theorems 1.2 and 1.3 and highlight the parallel with the original version of the Kruskal–Katona theorem. (οΈ€ )οΈ€ Let us mention that we state Theorem 2.3 only for 𝛾(β„±) ≀ π‘›βˆ’4 , since Theorem 1.3 (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’2)οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’3)οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’4)οΈ€ π‘˜βˆ’3 already gives us the bound |β„±| ≀ π‘˜βˆ’2 + 2 π‘˜βˆ’2 if 𝛾(β„±) β‰₯ π‘˜βˆ’3 , and we cannot get any better bound in general for larger 𝛾. Indeed, the intersecting family β„‹2 (cf. (1.1)) attains (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’3)οΈ€ the bound above on the cardinality and has diversity π‘˜βˆ’2 . The second part of Corollary 1.4 complements Theorem 1.3 in this respect, showing the aforementioned example is essentially the only exception. We also note that in a recent work [41] the author managed (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’3)οΈ€to prove that there exists 𝑐, such that for any 𝑛, π‘˜ satisfying 𝑛 β‰₯ π‘π‘˜ we have 𝛾(β„±) ≀ π‘˜βˆ’2 for any (οΈ€ )οΈ€ intersecting β„± βŠ‚ [𝑛] . Earlier, this was shown to be true for 𝑛 β‰₯ 6π‘˜ 2 by Frankl [17]. Thus, π‘˜ for 𝑛 β‰₯ π‘π‘˜ Theorem 2.3 gives a complete answer to the question we address. In Section 2.3, we shall analyze the cases when the equality in (2.1) can be attained, as well as the cases of very large diversity. In particular, we shall prove the 𝑒 = 3 part of Corollary 1.4. 2.1. Some examples and Theorem 2.3 restated. Let us try to familiarize the reader with the statement of Theorem(οΈ€ 2.3. )οΈ€We (οΈ€have )︀𝛾𝑖 = 𝑖 for 𝑖 = )οΈ€1, . . . , π‘˜ βˆ’ 3. Indeed, for (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’π›Ύ π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 1 ≀ 𝛾 < 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜ βˆ’ 1 we have 𝛾 = π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 + + . . . + . Thus, for any such 𝛾 we π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’π›Ύ have 𝑇𝛾 = [π‘˜ + 1, π‘˜ + 𝛾] and 𝑆𝛾 = [2, π‘˜] βˆͺ {𝛾}. Condition (1) in Definition 1 is satisfied if 𝛾 ≀ π‘˜ βˆ’ 1. Condition (2) is satisfied iff π‘˜ + 𝛾 > 2𝛾 + 2, which is equivalent to 𝛾 ≀ π‘˜ βˆ’ 3. (Note also that 𝛾 = 1 is resistant for π‘˜)οΈ€ = 3.) From the discussion above, we also conclude (οΈ€ π‘›βˆ’π‘˜ that, for π‘˜ > 3, we have π›Ύπ‘˜βˆ’2 = π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 = 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜. The following observation is given for the sake of familiarizing the reader with the statement. Observation. The bound in (οΈ€Theorem 2.3 is always at least )οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’4as )οΈ€ strong as the bound in Theorem 1.3 for intersecting β„± βŠ‚ [𝑛] with diversity 𝛾(β„±) ≀ . π‘˜ π‘˜βˆ’3 Let(οΈ€us first )οΈ€ compare the statement of Theorem 2.3 with the statement of Theorem 1.3 for π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1 𝛾𝑙 := π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 with integer 𝑒. Such 𝛾𝑙 is resistant for any 𝑒 ∈ [3, π‘˜], and we have 𝐴𝛾𝑙 = [2, 𝑒+1]. Thus, if we substitute such 𝛾𝑙 in (2.1), then we get the bound (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’2 π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1 |β„±| ≀ + ... + + 𝛾𝑙 = βˆ’ + , π‘›βˆ’π‘˜ π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’π‘’+1 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜ π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’π‘’ π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 which is exactly the bound (1.2) for 𝛾𝑙 . Remark that the inequality (2.1), however, gives a stronger conclusion and is valid in weaker assumptions. Indeed, while we know that this bound is sharp for 𝛾(β„±) = 𝛾𝑙 , Theorem 2.3 also tells us that β„± with 𝛾(β„±) > 𝛾𝑙 has strictly smaller size (quantified in Corollary 1.4). Moreover, even if π›Ύπ‘™βˆ’1 < 𝛾(β„±) ≀ 𝛾𝑙 , we are still getting the same upper bound. Returning to the proof of the observation, assume now that 𝑒 is a real number. The function in the right hand side of (1.2) is monotone decreasing as 𝛾(β„±) increases (or, equivalently, as 𝑒 decreases). Therefore, to show that the bound (2.1) is stronger than (1.2), it is sufficient to verify it for all values of 𝛾𝑙 , 𝑙 = 0, . . . , π‘š. But for each of these values the bound (2.1) is sharp, so (1.2) can be only weaker than (2.1). Proof of the first part of (οΈ€Corollary (integer) 𝑒 β‰₯)οΈ€ 4. )οΈ€ 1.4. Here, we prove Corollary 1.4 for (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1 )οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1 Choose 𝑙 such that 𝛾𝑙 = π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 . Assume first that π‘˜ β‰₯ 5. Then 𝛾𝑙+1 = π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 + π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 = (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1)οΈ€ + 1 =: 𝛾. To see this, we just have to check that 𝛾 is a resistant number. In terms π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 of Definition 1, we have 𝑇𝛾 = {𝑒 + 1, π‘˜ + 2} and 𝑆𝛾 = {2, 3, . . . , 𝑒, 𝑒 + 2 . . . , π‘˜ + 2}. We have 𝑠𝑏 = 2 ≀ π‘˜ βˆ’ 1 and π‘ π‘Ž = π‘˜, thus, condition (1) of Definition 1 is fulfilled. Moreover, 𝑏1 = 𝑒 + 1 > 2 Β· 1 + 2 and 𝑏2 = π‘˜ + 2 > 2 Β· 2 + 2, fulfilling condition (2) of the definition.

Thus, (2.1) implies that (οΈ‚

)οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘›βˆ’2 π‘›βˆ’π‘’ π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’2 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1 |β„±| ≀ + ... + + + ... + + +1 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜ π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’π‘’+2 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’π‘’+1 𝑛 βˆ’ 2π‘˜ + 1 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘›βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1 = βˆ’ + + 1 βˆ’ πœ–, π‘›βˆ’π‘˜ π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’π‘˜ π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1

where (οΈ‚ πœ–=

)οΈ‚ (︁(οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘’βˆ’2 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜ βˆ’ 2 )︁ π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 βˆ’ + ... + = = . π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’π‘’+1 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’π‘’+1 𝑛 βˆ’ 2π‘˜ + 1 𝑛 βˆ’ 2π‘˜ π‘˜βˆ’2

If π‘˜ = 4 then 𝑒 = 4 and 𝛾𝑙+1 = (οΈ‚ |β„±| ≀

)οΈ‚

(οΈ€π‘›βˆ’4)οΈ€ π‘˜βˆ’3

=

(οΈ€π‘›βˆ’4)οΈ€ . We get that 1

(οΈ‚

)οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘›βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’4 π‘›βˆ’4 π‘›βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’5 π‘›βˆ’5 βˆ’ + = βˆ’ + βˆ’ πœ–, π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘˜βˆ’3 π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘˜βˆ’4

where (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘›βˆ’5 π‘›βˆ’5 π‘›βˆ’5 π‘›βˆ’5 π‘›βˆ’6 πœ–= βˆ’ = βˆ’ = βˆ’ 1. π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’3 2 1 2

The second part of the corollary is proved in Section 2.3.



Our next goal is to state the β€œconceptual” version of Theorem 2.3. It requires certain preparations. We will use the framework and some of the ideas from [21], as well as from [43]. First of all, we switch to the cross-intersecting setting. Given an intersecting family β„± with βˆ†(β„±) = 𝛿1 (β„±), consider the families β„±(1) :={𝐹 βˆ– {1} : 1 ∈ 𝐹 ∈ β„±} Β― :={𝐹 : 1 ∈ β„±(1) / 𝐹 ∈ β„±}.

and

Remark that 𝛾(β„±) = |β„±(Β―1)|. Applying Theorem 2.1, from now on and until the end of Section 2 we assume that β„±(1) = β„’([2, 𝑛], |β„±(1)|, π‘˜ βˆ’ 1) and β„±(Β―1) = β„’([2, 𝑛], |β„±(Β―1)|, π‘˜). Note that β„±(1), β„±(Β―1) βŠ‚ 2[2,𝑛] . For shorthand, we denote π’œ := β„±(1), ℬ := β„±(Β―1). While proving Theorem 2.3, we will work with the ground set [2, 𝑛], in order not to confuse the reader and to keep clear the relationship between the diversity of intersecting families and the sizes of pairs of cross-intersecting families. Both π’œ and ℬ are determined by their lexicographically last set. In this section, we use the lexicographical/containment order on 2[2,𝑛] , which is defined as follows: 𝐴 β‰Ί 𝐡 iff 𝐴 βŠƒ 𝐡 or the minimal element of π΄βˆ–π΅ is smaller than the minimal element of 𝐡 βˆ–π΄. Let us recall some notions and results from [21] related to the Kruskal–Katona theorem and cross-intersecting families. For sets 𝑆 and 𝑋, |𝑆 ∩ 𝑋| ≀ π‘Ž, we define (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {︁ }︁ 𝑋 β„’(𝑋, 𝑆, π‘Ž) := 𝐴 ∈ : π΄β‰Ίπ‘†βˆ©π‘‹ . π‘Ž (οΈ€ )οΈ€ For example, the family {𝐺 ∈ [2,𝑛] : 2 ∈ 𝐺, 𝐺 ∩ {3, 4} ΜΈ= βˆ…} is the same as the family 10 β„’([2, 𝑛], 𝑆, 10) for 𝑆 = {1, 2, 4}. If 𝒒 = β„’(𝑋, 𝑆, π‘Ž) for a certain set 𝑆, then we say that 𝑆 is the characteristic set of 𝒒. Note that, in what follows, we shall work with 𝑋 = [2, 𝑛] and will omit 𝑋 from the notation for shorthand. For convenience, we shall assume that 1 ∈ 𝑆 (motivated by the fact that 𝑆 will stand for the characteristic set for the subfamily of all sets containing 1 in the original family), while 𝑇 βŠ‚ [2, 𝑛]. Definition 2. We say that two sets 𝑆 βŠ‚ [𝑛] and 𝑇 βŠ‚ [2, 𝑛] form a resistant pair, if either 𝑇 = {2, 3, 4} and 𝑆 = {1, 4}, or the following holds: assuming that the largest element of 𝑇 is 𝑗, we have (1) 𝑆 ∩ 𝑇 = {𝑗}, 𝑆 βˆͺ 𝑇 = [𝑗], |𝑆| ≀ π‘˜, |𝑇 | ≀ π‘˜; (2) for each 𝑖 β‰₯ 4, we have |[𝑖] ∩ 𝑆| < |[𝑖] βˆ– 𝑆|.

Condition (2), roughly speaking, states that in [𝑖] there are more elements in 𝑇 than in 𝑆. Note that 2 implies that 𝑇 βŠƒ {2, 3, 4} for each resistant pair. There is a close relationship between this notion and the notion of a resistant number, which we discuss a bit later. Let us first give the characteristic set version of Theorem 2.3. For convenience, we put 𝑇0 = [2, 𝑛] to be the characteristic set of the empty family and 𝑆0 := {1, 𝑛} to be the characteristic set (οΈ€ )οΈ€ of the family [2,𝑛] . π‘Ž Theorem 2.4. Let 𝑛 > 2π‘˜ β‰₯ 6. Consider all resistant pairs 𝑆𝑙 βŠ‚ [𝑛], 𝑇𝑙 βŠ‚ [2, 𝑛], where 𝑙 ∈ [π‘š]. Assume that 𝑇0 < 𝑇1 < 𝑇2 < . . . < π‘‡π‘š . Then |β„’(π‘†π‘™βˆ’1 , π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)| + |β„’(π‘‡π‘™βˆ’1 , π‘˜)| > |β„’(𝑆𝑙 , π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)| + |β„’(𝑇𝑙 , π‘˜)| for each 𝑙 ∈ [π‘š], (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€[2,𝑛])οΈ€ and any cross-intersecting pair of families π’œ βŠ‚ [2,𝑛] , ℬ βŠ‚ with |β„’(π‘‡π‘™βˆ’1 , π‘˜)| < |ℬ| ≀ π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘˜ |β„’(𝑇𝑙 , π‘˜)| satisfies (2.2)

|π’œ| + |ℬ| ≀ |β„’(𝑆𝑙 , π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)| + |β„’(𝑇𝑙 , π‘˜)|. (οΈ€ )οΈ€ In terms of intersecting families, if β„± βŠ‚ [𝑛] is intersecting and |β„’(π‘‡π‘™βˆ’1 , π‘˜)| < 𝛾(β„±) ≀ π‘˜ |β„’(𝑇𝑙 , π‘˜)|, then |β„±| ≀ |β„’(𝑆𝑙 , π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)| + |β„’(𝑇𝑙 , π‘˜)|.

(2.3)

First, we remark that the intersecting part is clearly equivalent to the second statement of the cross-intersecting part. Second, Proposition 2.5 below shows that the families 𝐿(𝑆𝑙 , π‘˜ βˆ’1) and 𝐿(𝑇𝑙 , π‘˜) are cross-intersecting and thus (2.3) is sharp. We say that two sets 𝑆 and 𝑇 in [2, 𝑛] strongly intersect, if there exists a positive integer 𝑗 such that 𝑆 ∩ 𝑇 ∩ [2, 𝑗] = {𝑗} and 𝑆 βˆͺ 𝑇 βŠƒ [2, 𝑗]. The following proposition was proven in [21]: Proposition 2.5 ([21]). Let 𝐴 and 𝐡 be subsets of [2, 𝑛], |𝐴| ≀ π‘Ž, |𝐡| ≀ 𝑏, and |[2, 𝑛]| = 𝑛 βˆ’ 1 β‰₯ π‘Ž + 𝑏. Then β„’(𝑃, π‘Ž) and β„’(𝑄, 𝑏) are cross-intersecting iff 𝑃 and 𝑄 strongly intersect. Now let us deduce Theorem 2.3 from Theorem 2.4. Reduction of Theorem 2.3 to Theorem 2.4. Let us first compute the size of the family β„’(𝑇, π‘˜βˆ’ 1) for a given set 𝑇 ∈ [2, 𝑛]. Assume that 𝑏𝑠𝑏 is the largest element of 𝑇 and that [2, 𝑏𝑠𝑏 ] βˆ– 𝑇 = {𝑏1 , . . . , 𝑏𝑠𝑏 βˆ’1 }. Take the smallest element 𝑏1 ∈ [2, 𝑛] βˆ– 𝑇 and consider the family with characteristic := (𝑇 (οΈ€ π‘›βˆ’π‘1 )οΈ€set 𝑇(οΈ€1π‘›βˆ’π‘ )οΈ€ ∩ [𝑏1 ]) βˆͺ {𝑏1 }. Note that 𝑇1 = [2, 𝑏1 ] and thus the size of this family 1 is π‘˜βˆ’π‘1 +1 = π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 . Since 𝑇1 β‰Ί 𝑇 , this family is a subfamily of β„’(𝑇, π‘˜ βˆ’ 1). Proceeding iteratively, at each step take the next smallest (not chosen yet) element 𝑏𝑖 from [2, 𝑛] βˆ– 𝑇 and define the set 𝑇𝑖 := (𝑇 ∩ [𝑏 . Again, 𝑇𝑖 β‰Ί 𝑇 . Count the sets that belong to {︀𝑖 ]) βˆͺ 𝑏(︀𝑖[2,𝑛] )οΈ€ }οΈ€ β„’(𝑇 , π‘˜ βˆ’ 1) βˆ– 𝐿(𝑇 , π‘˜ βˆ’ 1) = 𝐹 ∈ π‘˜ : 𝐹 ∩ [𝑏𝑖 ] = 𝑇𝑖 . Their number is precisely (οΈ€ π‘›βˆ’π‘π‘– 𝑖 )οΈ€ (οΈ€ π‘›βˆ’π‘π‘– π‘–βˆ’1 )οΈ€ = π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’|[𝑏𝑖 ]βˆ–π‘‡π‘– | . Since we β€œstop” at every element that is not included in 𝑇 , we get π‘˜βˆ’|𝑇𝑖 | (οΈ€ π‘›βˆ’π‘π‘– )οΈ€ (οΈ€ π‘›βˆ’π‘π‘– )οΈ€ that |[𝑏𝑖 ] βˆ– 𝑇𝑖 | = |[π‘π‘–βˆ’1 βˆ– π‘‡π‘–βˆ’1 | + 1 = . . . = 𝑖. Therefore, π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’|[𝑏 = π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’π‘– . We stop the 𝑖 ]βˆ–π‘‡π‘– | )οΈ€ (οΈ€[2,𝑛] procedure at the point when 𝑇𝑖 = 𝑇 , including the sets 𝐹 ∈ π‘˜βˆ’1 that satisfy 𝐹 ∩ [𝑏𝑠𝑏 ] = 𝑇 in the count. It should be clear that, in this counting procedure, we counted each set from β„’(𝑇, π‘˜ βˆ’ 1) exactly once. We get that (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ 𝑛 βˆ’ 𝑏1 𝑛 βˆ’ 𝑏2 𝑛 βˆ’ 𝑏𝑠 𝑏 |β„’(𝑇, π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)| = + + ... + , π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜ βˆ’ 𝑠𝑏 and the displayed formula gives the representation of |β„’(𝑇, π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)| in the (𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)-cascade form! Moreover, we conclude that the set {𝑏1 , . . . , 𝑏𝑠𝑏 } is exactly the set 𝑇𝛾 for 𝛾 := |β„’(𝑇, π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)| (cf. the paragraph above Definition 1). We have 𝑇𝛾 = ([2, 𝑏𝑠𝑏 ] βˆ– 𝑇 ) βˆͺ {𝑏𝑠𝑏 } and thus 𝑇 = 𝑆𝛾 . Therefore, if 𝑆, 𝑇 is a resistant pair, then, putting 𝛾 := |β„’(𝑇, π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)|, we get that 𝑇 = 𝑆𝛾 and 𝑆 ∩ [2, 𝑛] = 𝑇𝛾 . This immediately implies that 𝑇𝛾 and 𝑆𝛾 satisfy condition (1) of Definition 1. The implication in the other direction follows as well. Condition (2) of

Definition 2 is equivalent to the statement that 1 + |𝑇𝛾 ∩ [𝑖]| < |[2, 𝑖] βˆ– 𝑇𝛾 | for each 𝑖 (οΈ€β‰₯ 4,)οΈ€ which, in turn, is equivalent to 𝑏𝑙 > 2𝑙 + 2 for each 𝑙 β‰₯ 1. Finally, it is clear that 𝛾 = π‘›βˆ’4 π‘˜βˆ’3 correspond to the characteristic set {2, 3, 4}. We conclude that 𝑇𝑙 and 𝑆𝑙 form a resistant pair if and only if |β„’(𝑇𝑙 , π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)| is a resistant number. Doing calculations as above, one can conclude that (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘Ž1 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘Ž2 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘Žπ‘  π‘Ž |β„’(𝑆𝑙 , π‘˜)| = + + ... + , π‘›βˆ’π‘˜ π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜ βˆ’ π‘ π‘Ž + 1 where π‘Žπ‘– are as in the statement of Theorem 2.3. Given that, it is clear that the inequality (2.2) is equivalent to the statement saying that the right hand side of (2.1) is strictly monotone, and that (2.1) is equivalent to (2.3). Finally, the sharpness claimed in Theorem 2.3 immediately follows from the remark in the paragraph after Theorem 2.4.  (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€ )οΈ€ 2.2. Proof of Theorem 2.4. We say that π’œ βŠ‚ [2,𝑛] and ℬ βŠ‚ [2,𝑛] form a maximal π‘Ž 𝑏 (οΈ€[2,𝑛])οΈ€ (οΈ€[2,𝑛])οΈ€ β€² β€² cross-intersecting pair, if, whenever π’œ βŠ‚ π‘Ž and ℬ βŠ‚ 𝑏 are cross-intersecting with π’œβ€² βŠƒ π’œ and ℬ β€² βŠƒ ℬ, then necessarily π’œ = π’œβ€² and ℬ = ℬ β€² holds. The following proposition from [21] is another important step in our analysis. Proposition 2.6 ([21]). Let π‘Ž and 𝑏 be positive integers, π‘Ž + 𝑏 ≀ 𝑛 βˆ’ 1. Let 𝑃 and 𝑄 be non-empty subsets of [2, 𝑛] with |𝑃 | ≀ π‘Ž, |𝑄| ≀ 𝑏. Suppose that 𝑃 and 𝑄 strongly intersect in their largest element, that is, there exists 𝑗 such that 𝑃 ∩ 𝑄 = {𝑗} and 𝑃 βˆͺ 𝑄 = [2, 𝑗]. Then β„’([2, 𝑛], 𝑃, π‘Ž) and β„’([2, 𝑛], 𝑄, 𝑏) form a maximal pair of cross-intersecting families. Inversely, if β„’([2, 𝑛], π‘š, π‘Ž) and β„’([2, 𝑛], π‘Ÿ, 𝑏) form a maximal pair of cross-intersecting families, then there exist sets 𝑃 and 𝑄 that strongly intersect in their largest element, such that β„’([2, 𝑛], π‘š, π‘Ž) = β„’([2, 𝑛], 𝑃, π‘Ž), β„’([2, 𝑛], π‘Ÿ, 𝑏) = β„’([2, 𝑛], 𝑄, 𝑏). Recall that we aim to maximize |π’œ| + |ℬ| given a lower bound on |ℬ|. The proof is based on the following two lemmas. (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€ )οΈ€ Lemma 2.7. Consider a pair of cross-intersecting families π’œ βŠ‚ [2,𝑛] , ℬ βŠ‚ [2,𝑛] . Suppose π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘˜ that π’œ = β„’(𝑆, π‘˜ βˆ’ 1), ℬ = β„’(𝑇, π‘˜) for some sets 𝑆 βŠ‚ [𝑛], 𝑇 βŠ‚ [2, 𝑛] that strongly intersect in their last element 𝑗. Suppose also that 𝑇  {2, 3, 4}. Assume that βƒ’ βƒ’ 𝑆⃒ and 𝑇⃒ do not form a resistant pair, that is, there exists 5 ≀ 𝑖 ≀ 𝑗, such that βƒ’[𝑖] ∩ 𝑆 βƒ’ β‰₯ βƒ’[𝑖] βˆ– 𝑆 βƒ’. Put 𝑇 β€² := [𝑖] βˆ– 𝑆 and choose 𝑆 β€² so that it strongly intersects with (οΈ€ )οΈ€ β€² (οΈ€[2,𝑛])οΈ€ 𝑇 β€² in its largest element. Then the families π’œβ€² βŠ‚ [2,𝑛] , ℬ βŠ‚ π‘˜ with characteristic sets π‘˜βˆ’1 β€² β€² 𝑆 β€² , 𝑇 β€² are cross-intersecting and satisfy |π’œ | + |ℬ | β‰₯ |π’œ| + |ℬ| and |ℬ β€² | > |ℬ|. βƒ’ βƒ’ βƒ’ βƒ’ Moreover, if βƒ’[𝑖] ∩ 𝑆 βƒ’ > βƒ’[𝑖] βˆ– 𝑆 βƒ’ then |π’œβ€² | + |ℬ β€² | > |π’œ| + |ℬ|. Proof of Lemma 2.7. First, recall that 1 ∈ 𝑆. Since 𝑆 β€² and 𝑇 β€² are strongly intersecting, the families π’œβ€² , ℬ β€² are cross-intersecting. Next, clearly, 𝑇 β€² ( 𝑇 and thus ℬ β€² ) ℬ. Therefore, we only have to prove that |π’œ| + |ℬ| ≀ |π’œβ€² | + |ℬ β€² |, and that the inequality is strict in the case indicated in the lemma. Consider the following families: (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {οΈ€ }οΈ€ [2, 𝑛] π’«π‘Ž := 𝑃 ∈ : 𝑃 ∩ [𝑖] = [2, 𝑖] ∩ 𝑆 , π‘˜βˆ’1 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {οΈ€ }οΈ€ [2, 𝑛] 𝒫𝑏 := 𝑃 ∈ : 𝑃 ∩ [𝑖] = [𝑖] βˆ– 𝑆 . π‘˜ We have π’œ βˆ– π’«π‘Ž = π’œβ€² , ℬ βˆͺ 𝒫𝑏 = ℬ β€² . Both equalities are proved in the same way, so let us show, e.g., the first one. We have 𝑆 β€² β‰Ί 𝑆 β‰Ί 𝑆 ∩ [𝑖], therefore π’œβ€² βŠ‚ π’œ βŠ‚ β„’(𝑆 ∩ [𝑖], π‘˜ βˆ’ 1). On the other hand, we claim that 𝑆 β€² and 𝑆 ∩ [𝑖] are two consecutive sets in the lexicographic order on [𝑖]. Indeed, assume that the largest element of 𝑇 β€² is 𝑗 β€² . If 𝑗 β€² = 𝑖, then 𝑆 β€² βŠƒ 𝑆 ∩ [𝑖],

(𝑆 β€² βˆ– 𝑆) ∩ [𝑖] = {𝑖}, which proves it in this case. If 𝑗 β€² < 𝑖, then [𝑗 β€² + 1, 𝑖] βŠ‚ 𝑆 ∩ [𝑖], 𝑗 β€² ∈ / 𝑆 ∩ [𝑖]. It is easy to see that the set that precedes 𝑆 ∩ [𝑖] in the lexicographic order on [𝑖] β€œreplaces” [𝑗 β€² + 1, 𝑖] with {𝑗 β€² }, that is, it is 𝑆 β€² . Therefore, π’œ βˆ– π’œβ€² βŠ‚ β„’(𝑆 ∩ [𝑖], π‘˜ βˆ’ 1) βˆ– π’œβ€² = β„’(𝑆 ∩ [𝑖], π‘˜ βˆ’ 1) βˆ– β„’(𝑆 β€² , π‘˜ βˆ’ 1) = π’«π‘Ž , which, together with the fact that π’«π‘Ž and π’œβ€² are disjoint, is equivalent to the equality we aimed to prove. Next, consider the bipartite graph 𝐺 with parts π’«π‘Ž , 𝒫𝑏 and edges connecting disjoint sets. Then, due to the fact that π’œ and ℬ are cross-intersecting, (π’œβˆ©π’«π‘Ž )βˆͺ(β„¬βˆ©π’«π‘ ) is an independent set in 𝐺. The graph 𝐺 is (οΈ€biregular, and(οΈ€therefore the largest independent set in 𝐺 is one of its parts. )οΈ€ )οΈ€ π‘›βˆ’π‘– π‘›βˆ’π‘– We have |π’«π‘Ž | = π‘ π‘Ž , |𝒫𝑏 | = 𝑠𝑏 , where π‘ π‘Ž = π‘˜ βˆ’ |[𝑖] ∩ 𝑆|, 𝑠𝑏 = π‘˜ βˆ’ |[𝑖] βˆ– 𝑆|. By the condition from the lemma, we have 𝑠𝑏 β‰₯ π‘ π‘Ž , and, since 𝑛 βˆ’ 𝑖 > π‘ π‘Ž + 𝑠𝑏 , we have |𝒫𝑏 | β‰₯ |π’«π‘Ž |. We conclude that |𝒫𝑏 | is the largest independent set in 𝐺, so |𝒫𝑏 | β‰₯ (π’œ ∩ π’«π‘Ž ) βˆͺ (ℬ ∩ 𝒫𝑏 ), and therefore |π’œβ€² | + |ℬ β€² | βˆ’ (|π’œ| + |ℬ|) = |𝒫𝑏 | βˆ’ |π’œ ∩ π’«π‘Ž | βˆ’ |ℬ ∩ 𝒫𝑏 | β‰₯ 0. βƒ’ βƒ’ βƒ’ βƒ’ If βƒ’[𝑖] βˆ– 𝑆 βƒ’ < ⃒𝑆 ∩ [𝑖]βƒ’, then |𝒫𝑏 | > |π’«π‘Ž | and 𝒫𝑏 is the unique independent set of maximal size in 𝐺. Thus, we have strict inequality in the displayed inequality above.  Slightly abusing notation, we say that π’œ, ℬ form a resistant pair if the corresponding characteristic sets form a resistant pair. The second lemma describes how do the resistant pairs behave. More specifically, it shows that (2.2) holds: the sum of sizes of resistant cross-intersecting families increases as the size of the second family decreases. (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€ )οΈ€ Lemma 2.8. Consider a resistant pair of cross-intersecting families π’œ βŠ‚ [2,𝑛] , ℬ βŠ‚ [2,𝑛] , π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘˜ with characteristic sets)οΈ€ 𝑆 βŠ‚ [𝑛], 𝑇 βŠ‚ [2, 𝑛], respectively, and another such resistant pair (οΈ€[2,𝑛])οΈ€ β€² (οΈ€[2,𝑛] β€² π’œ βŠ‚ π‘˜βˆ’1 , ℬ βŠ‚ π‘˜ with characteristic sets 𝑆 β€² βŠ‚ [𝑛], 𝑇 β€² βŠ‚ [2, 𝑛]. If 𝑇 β€²  𝑇 , then |ℬ β€² | < |ℬ| and |π’œ| + |ℬ| < |π’œβ€² | + |ℬ β€² |. Therefore, while for general lexicographic pairs of families the sum of sizes is not monotone w.r.t. the size of the second family, it is monotone for resistant pairs. Remark that, since 𝑇 β€²  𝑇 , we have 𝑇 β€² ΜΈ= {2, 3, 4} and thus 𝑆 β€² , 𝑇 β€² must satisfy Condition (2) of Definition 2. We also note that we do not use the property that 𝑆, 𝑇 form a resistant pair. The proof also works for 𝑇 β€² = 𝑇0 (recall that 𝑇0 = [2, 𝑛]). The proof of this lemma is based on biregular bipartite graphs and is very similar to the proof of Lemma 2.7, although is a bit trickier. Proof of Lemma 2.8. First, it is clear that, in the conditions of the lemma, we have |ℬ β€² | < |ℬ|. The rest of the proof is concerned with the inequality on the sums of sizes. We consider two cases depending on how do the sets 𝑇 and 𝑇 β€² relate. Case 1. 𝑇 β€² + 𝑇 . Note that this condition, in particular, implies that 𝑇 ΜΈ= {2, 3, 4}. Find the smallest 𝑖 β‰₯ 5, such that exactly one of the sets 𝑇, 𝑇 β€² contain 𝑖. Since 𝑇 β€² β‰Ί 𝑇 , we clearly have 𝑖 ∈ 𝑇 β€² , 𝑖 ∈ / 𝑇 . Consider the set 𝑇 β€²β€² = 𝑇 β€² ∩ [𝑖]. Then we clearly have 𝑇 β€²  𝑇 β€²β€²  𝑇 and 𝑇 β€²β€² βŠ‚ 𝑇(οΈ€β€² . Accordingly, put 𝑆 β€²β€² to be {𝑖}βˆͺ([𝑖]βˆ–π‘‡ β€²β€² ), and consider the cross-intersecting families )οΈ€ (οΈ€ )οΈ€ [2,𝑛] [2,𝑛] π’œβ€²β€² βŠ‚ π‘˜βˆ’1 , ℬ β€²β€² βŠ‚ π‘˜ , which have characteristic vectors 𝑆 β€²β€² and 𝑇 β€²β€² , respectively. Note that 𝑆 β€²β€² = 𝑆 ∩ [𝑖] and thus the pair π’œβ€²β€² , ℬ β€²β€² is resistant. We claim that |π’œβ€²β€² | + |ℬ β€²β€² | > |π’œ| + |ℬ|. We prove the inequality above as in Lemma 2.7, but the roles of 𝑆 and 𝑇 are now switched. Consider the bipartite graph 𝐺 with parts

)οΈ‚ }οΈ€ [2, 𝑛] : 𝑃 ∩ [𝑖] = [2, 𝑖] βˆ– 𝑇 , π‘˜βˆ’1 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {οΈ€ }οΈ€ [2, 𝑛] 𝒫𝑏 := 𝑃 ∈ : 𝑃 ∩ [𝑖] = [𝑖] ∩ 𝑇 , π‘˜

{οΈ€ π’«π‘Ž := 𝑃 ∈

(οΈ‚

and edges connecting disjoint sets. Similarly, we have π’œ βˆͺ π’«π‘Ž = π’œβ€²β€² , ℬ βˆ– 𝒫𝑏 = ℬ β€²β€² . Indeed, let us verify, e.g., the second equality. All π‘˜-element sets 𝑃 such that 𝑃 β‰Ί 𝑇 β€²β€² are in ℬ and in ℬ βˆ– 𝒫𝑏 , as well as in ℬ β€²β€² , since 𝑇 β€²β€²  𝑇 ∩ [𝑖]. On the other hand, if we restrict to [𝑖], the sets 𝑇 ∩ [𝑖] and 𝑇 β€²β€² are consecutive in the lexicographic order, and so any set 𝐡 from ℬ such that 𝐡  𝑇 β€²β€² must satisfy 𝐡 ∩ [𝑖] = 𝑇 ∩ [𝑖]. Therefore, ℬ βˆ– ℬ β€²β€² βŠ‚ 𝒫𝑏 and ℬ βˆ– 𝒫𝑏 = ℬ β€²β€² . The families π’œ and ℬ are cross-intersecting, and so the set (π’œβˆ©π’«π‘Ž )βˆͺ(β„¬βˆ©π’«π‘ ) is independent in 𝐺. On the other hand, the largest independent set in 𝐺 has size max{|π’«π‘Ž |, |𝒫𝑏 |}. Since β€²β€² β€²β€² the pair π’œβ€² , ℬ β€²(οΈ€is resistant, )οΈ€ (οΈ€ weπ‘›βˆ’π‘–have )οΈ€ that |[𝑖] ∩ 𝑇 | = |[𝑖] βˆ– 𝑆 | > |[𝑖] ∩ 𝑆 | = |[𝑖] βˆ– 𝑇 |, which π‘›βˆ’π‘– implies |π’«π‘Ž | = π‘˜βˆ’|[𝑖]βˆ–π‘‡ | > π‘˜βˆ’|[𝑖]βˆ©π‘‡ | = |𝒫𝑏 |, and thus π’«π‘Ž is the (unique) largest independent set in 𝐺. We have |π’œβ€²β€² | + |ℬ β€²β€² | βˆ’ (|π’œ| + |ℬ|) = |π’«π‘Ž | βˆ’ |π’œ ∩ π’«π‘Ž | βˆ’ |ℬ ∩ 𝒫𝑏 | > 0, and the desired inequality is proven. Therefore, when comparing 𝑇 β€² and 𝑇 , we may replace 𝑇 with 𝑇 β€²β€² , or rather assume that 𝑇 βŠ‚ 𝑇 β€² . We have reduced Case 1 to the following case. Case 2. 𝑇 β€² βŠƒ 𝑇 . 6 Assume that 𝑑1 < 𝑑2 < . . . < 𝑑𝑙 are the elements forming the set 𝑇 β€² βˆ– 𝑇 and let 𝑑0 be the largest element of 𝑇 . Let us first show that, for each 𝑖 ∈ [𝑙 βˆ’ 1], we have |[𝑑𝑖 ] βˆ– 𝑆 β€² | β‰₯ |[𝑑𝑖 ] ∩ 𝑆 β€² | + 2. Indeed, find the largest element 𝑑′ < 𝑑𝑖 , such that 𝑑′ ∈ 𝑆 β€² . We have |[𝑑𝑖 ] βˆ– 𝑆 β€² | > |[𝑑′ ] βˆ– 𝑆 β€² | > |[𝑑′ ] ∩ 𝑆 β€² | = |[𝑑𝑖 ] ∩ 𝑆 β€² |. For 𝑖 = 0, . . . , 𝑙, put 𝑆𝑖 := [𝑑𝑖 ] ∩ 𝑆 β€² βˆͺ {𝑑𝑖 } and 𝑇𝑖 := 𝑇 β€² ∩ [𝑑𝑖 ]. Observe that, for each 𝑖 ∈ [𝑙], we have |[𝑑𝑖 ] βˆ– 𝑆𝑖 | β‰₯ |[𝑑𝑖 ] ∩ 𝑆𝑖 | by the displayed (οΈ€[2,𝑛])οΈ€ inequality. (οΈ€[2,𝑛])οΈ€ Moreover, the inequality is strict for 𝑖 = 𝑙. For each 𝑖 = 0, . . . , 𝑙, let π’œπ‘– βŠ‚ π‘˜βˆ’1 , ℬ𝑖 βŠ‚ π‘˜ be the pair of cross-intersecting families defined by characteristic sets 𝑆𝑖 , 𝑇𝑖 . Observe that π’œ0 = π’œ, ℬ0 = ℬ and π’œπ‘™ = π’œβ€² , ℬ𝑙 = ℬ β€² . Finally, for each 𝑖 ∈ [𝑙], we show that |π’œπ‘– | + |ℬ𝑖 | β‰₯ |π’œπ‘–βˆ’1 | + |β„¬π‘–βˆ’1 |, moreover, the inequality is strict for 𝑖 = 𝑙. This is clearly sufficient to conclude the proof of the lemma. Consider the bipartite graph 𝐺 with parts (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {οΈ€ }οΈ€ [2, 𝑛] 𝑖 π’«π‘Ž := 𝑃 ∈ : 𝑃 ∩ [𝑖] = 𝑆𝑖 ∩ [2, 𝑖] , π‘˜βˆ’1 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {οΈ€ }οΈ€ [2, 𝑛] 𝑖 𝒫𝑏 := 𝑃 ∈ : 𝑃 ∩ [𝑖] = [𝑖] βˆ– 𝑆𝑖 , π‘˜ and edges connecting disjoint sets. As before, we have π’œπ‘–βˆ’1 βˆͺ π’«π‘Žπ‘– = π’œπ‘– , β„¬π‘–βˆ’1 βˆ– 𝒫𝑏𝑖 = ℬ𝑖 . Using the fact that |[𝑖] βˆ– 𝑆𝑖 | β‰₯ |[𝑖] ∩ 𝑆𝑖 | and that this inequality is strict for 𝑖 = 𝑙, we conclude the proof as in the previous case.  Now let us put the things together. Proof of Theorem 2.4. First, (2.2) follows from Lemma 2.8. Next, given a pair of crossintersecting families π’œ, ℬ as in the theorem, we may assume using Theorem 2.1 and Proposition 2.6 that π’œ, ℬ are lexicographic families defined by characteristic sets 𝑆, 𝑇 that strongly intersect in their last coordinate. We may further assume that they do not form a resistant pair. Using Lemma 2.7 with the smallest 𝑖 satisfying its conditions, replace π’œ, ℬ with the 6We

note that, in this case, we do not use the fact that π’œ, ℬ form a resistant pair (and thus the proof works for 𝑇 = {2, 3, 4}).

corresponding pair π’œβ€² , ℬ β€² defined by characteristic sets 𝑆 β€² , 𝑇 β€² . Remark that 𝑇  𝑇 β€² and that, moreover, π’œβ€² , ℬ β€² form a resistant pair by the choice of 𝑖. (Note here that if 𝑖 = 5 then the resulting characteristic sets are 𝑇 β€² = π‘‡π‘š = {2, 3, 4} and 𝑆 β€² = π‘†π‘š = {1, 4}.) Therefore, if π‘‡π‘™βˆ’1  𝑇 then 𝑇𝑙 β‰Ί 𝑇 β€² , and therefore |β„’(𝑆𝑙 , π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)| + |β„’(𝑇𝑙 , π‘˜)| β‰₯ |π’œβ€² | + |ℬ β€² | β‰₯ |π’œ| + |ℬ|. This completes the proof of the theorem.  2.3. Equality in Theorems 2.3, 2.4 and families with large diversity. In the notations of the previous section, let π’œ, ℬ be cross-intersecting and defined by the characteristic sets 𝑆, 𝑇 , respectively, where |𝑆|, |𝑇 | ≀ π‘˜. In this section, we determine, for which 𝑇 , π‘‡π‘™βˆ’1 β‰Ί 𝑇 β‰Ί 𝑇𝑙 , it is possible to have equality in (2.3). Definition 3. We say that a pair of strongly intersecting sets 𝑆, 𝑇 as above is 𝑇𝑙 -neutral, if 𝑇 is obtained in the following recursive way: (1) 𝑇𝑙 is 𝑇𝑙 -neutral; (2) If 𝑇 β€² is 𝑇𝑙 -neutral, then the set 𝑇 := 𝑇 β€² βˆͺ {2|𝑇 β€² |} is 𝑇𝑙 -neutral. In other words, to form all 𝑇𝑙 -neutral sets, we start from the set 𝑇𝑙 , add the element 2|𝑇𝑙 | and then continue adding every other element until we have π‘˜ elements in the set. It is not difficult to see that any 𝑇𝑙 -neutral pair 𝑆, 𝑇 actually satisfies π‘‡π‘™βˆ’1  𝑇 β‰Ί 𝑇𝑙 . Let us also note that, in terms of Definition 3, each newly formed 𝑇𝑙 -neutral set is different from the previous one: indeed, from Definition 2, the largest element in 𝑇𝑙 is at most 2|𝑇𝑙 | βˆ’ 2 (actually, it is at most 2|𝑇𝑙 | βˆ’ 3 for all 𝑙 < π‘š and equal to 2|𝑇𝑙 | βˆ’ 2 in the case 𝑙 = π‘š), and every newly added element (by Condition (2) of Definition 3) is bigger by 2 than the previously added element. (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€ )οΈ€ Theorem 2.9. Let 𝑛 > 2π‘˜ β‰₯ 6. Consider a pair π’œ βŠ‚ [2,𝑛] , ℬ βŠ‚ [2,𝑛] defined by strongly π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘˜ intersecting sets 𝑆, 𝑇 that intersect in their largest element. If π‘‡π‘™βˆ’1 < 𝑇 ≀ 𝑇𝑙 for some 𝑙 ∈ [π‘š], then equality in (2.3) holds if and only if the pair 𝑆, 𝑇 is 𝑇𝑙 -neutral. Proof. First, let us show that, for any 𝑇𝑙 -neutral pair, we have equality in (2.3). We prove it inductively. It is clear for the pair with characteristic sets 𝑆, 𝑇 , where 𝑇 = 𝑇𝑙 . Assuming it holds for 𝑇 β€² , let us prove that it holds for 𝑇 := 𝑇 β€² βˆͺ {2|𝑇 β€² |}. Put π‘₯ := 2|𝑇 | and consider the pairs of cross-intersecting families π’œ, ℬ, π’œβ€² , ℬ β€² , corresponding to the 𝑇𝑙 -neutral pairs of sets 𝑆, 𝑇 and 𝑆 β€² , 𝑇 β€² , respectively. By Definition 3, we have |[π‘₯] ∩ 𝑆| = |[π‘₯] βˆ– 𝑆|. Therefore, applying the argument of Lemma 2.7 with (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {οΈ€ }οΈ€ [2, 𝑛] π’«π‘Ž := 𝑃 ∈ : 𝑃 ∩ [π‘₯] = [2, π‘₯] ∩ 𝑆 , π‘˜βˆ’1 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {οΈ€ }οΈ€ [2, 𝑛] 𝒫𝑏 := 𝑃 ∈ : 𝑃 ∩ [π‘₯] = [π‘₯] βˆ– 𝑆 , π‘˜ We get that π‘˜ βˆ’1βˆ’|[2, π‘₯]βˆ©π‘†| = π‘˜ βˆ’|[π‘₯]βˆ–π‘†|, which implies |π’«π‘Ž | = |𝒫𝑏 |. Moreover, π’œβˆ–π’œβ€² = π’«π‘Ž , ℬ βˆ– ℬ β€² = 𝒫𝑏 , since the sets 𝑆 β€² and 𝑆 are both subsets of [π‘₯] and are consecutive in the lexicographical order on [π‘₯] (and the same holds for 𝑇, 𝑇 β€² ). Therefore, |π’œβ€² | + |ℬ β€² | = |π’œ| + |ℬ|. In the other direction, take a set 𝑇 , π‘‡π‘™βˆ’1  𝑇  𝑇𝑙 , and its pair 𝑆. Consider the corresponding pair of cross-intersecting families π’œ, ℬ and assume that they satisfy equality in (2.3). Then it is easy to see that 𝑇 βŠƒ 𝑇𝑙 . (Otherwise, either 𝑇 ≻ 𝑇𝑙 , or 𝑇 must contain and thus succeed some other resistant set, which succeeds𝑇𝑙 , again contradicting 𝑇  𝑇𝑙 .) Assuming that π‘₯ is the last element in 𝑇 , we must have |[𝑖] ∩ 𝑆| < |[𝑖] βˆ– 𝑆|

for 5 ≀ 𝑖 ≀ π‘₯ βˆ’ 1.

Indeed, otherwise, considering the bipartite graph 𝐺 with parts π’«π‘Ž , 𝒫𝑏 as displayed above for that 𝑖, we would get that |π’«π‘Ž | ≀ |𝒫𝑏 | and both π’«π‘Ž ∩ π’œ and 𝒫𝑏 ∩ ℬ are non-empty. In this case |π’«π‘Ž ∩ π’œ| + |𝒫𝑏 ∩ ℬ| < |π’«π‘Ž |, which means that the pair π’œβ€² , ℬ β€² defined by the characteristic sets 𝑇 β€² := 𝑇 ∩ [𝑖] and its pair 𝑆 β€² would satisfy |π’œβ€² | + |ℬ β€² | > |π’œ| + |ℬ|. Moreover, 𝑇 β€² βŠƒ 𝑇𝑙 , so 𝑇  𝑇 β€² β‰Ί 𝑇𝑙 and |π’œβ€² | + |ℬ β€² | ≀ |β„’(𝑆𝑙 , π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)| + |β„’(𝑇𝑙 , π‘˜)|. This contradicts the equality for π’œ, ℬ in (2.3). Therefore, since the pair 𝑆, 𝑇 is not resistant, we have |[π‘₯] ∩ 𝑆| = |[π‘₯] βˆ– 𝑆|. (We cannot have β€œ>”, since otherwise we would have β€œβ‰₯” for 𝑖 = π‘₯ βˆ’ 1.) Removing π‘₯, we get a set 𝑇 β€² , and conclude that π‘₯ = 2|𝑇 β€² |. By induction on the size of the set 𝑇 , we may assume that 𝑇 β€² is 𝑇𝑙 -neutral. But then 𝑇 is 𝑇𝑙 -neutral as well.  A slight modification of the argument above leads to the proof of the second part of Corollary 1.4. Proof of the second part of Corollary 1.4. In the framework of the previous proofs, replace β„±(1), β„±(Β―1) with lexicographical families and put π’œ := β„±(1), ℬ := β„±(Β―1). For 𝑖 ∈ [3], let π’œπ‘– , ℬ𝑖 be the pairs of cross-intersecting families defined by characteristic sets (︀𝑇 𝑖 , 𝑆)︀𝑖 , where 𝑇 1 = π‘‡π‘š = {2, 3, 4}, 𝑇 2 = {2, 3} and 𝑇 3 = {2, 4}. It is easy to see that |ℬ1 | = π‘›βˆ’4 , |ℬ2 | = π‘˜βˆ’3 (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’3)οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’3)οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’4)οΈ€ and |ℬ3 | = π‘˜βˆ’2 + π‘˜βˆ’2 . π‘˜βˆ’2 (οΈ€ )οΈ€ If 𝛾(β„±) < π‘›βˆ’3 then consider the graph 𝐺 with parts π’«π‘Ž , 𝒫𝑏 , where the parts contains the π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜-element sets that intersect [4] in {1, 4} and in {2, 3}, respectively. Then |π’«π‘Ž | = |𝒫𝑏 | and π’œ1 βˆ– π’œ2 = π’«π‘Ž , ℬ2 βˆ– ℬ1 = 𝒫𝑏 . Moreover, (π’«π‘Ž ∩ π’œ) βˆͺ (𝒫𝑏 ∩ ℬ) is independent in 𝐺. Thus, if π’œβˆˆ / {π’œ1 , π’œ2 } then the aforementioned independent set is strictly smaller than π’«π‘Ž , 𝒫𝑏 , and thus |π’œ| + |ℬ| < |π’œπ‘– | + |ℬ𝑖 | for 𝑖 = 1, 2. Furthermore, provided that both π’«π‘Ž ∩ π’œ and 𝒫𝑏 ∩ ℬ are non-empty, then (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘›βˆ’4 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 |π’«π‘Ž ∩ π’œ| + |𝒫𝑏 ∩ ℬ| ≀ βˆ’ + 1. π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 This is easy to deduce from the Kruskal–Katona theorem and was proven already by Hilton and Milner For a more general statement, see Corollary 2.14 in Section 2.4. Since (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’4[33]. )οΈ€ 𝛾(β„±) > π‘˜βˆ’3 , 𝒫𝑏 ∩ ℬ is non-empty. If π’œ is non-empty then the displayed bound holds, and (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2)οΈ€ thus (1.3) is valid. If π’œ is empty then, using |ℬ| ≀ π‘›βˆ’4 βˆ’ π‘˜βˆ’2 + 1 (that immediately π‘˜βˆ’2 (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’3)οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2)οΈ€ follows from |β„±(Β―1)| ≀ π‘˜βˆ’2 βˆ’ π‘˜βˆ’2 + 1), we conclude that the displayed holds trivially. Thus, (1.3) is (οΈ€valid)οΈ€ in any case. If 𝛾(β„±) > π‘›βˆ’3 then we repeat the proof, but using the parts π’«π‘Ž , 𝒫𝑏 that contain the π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜-element sets that intersect [4] in {1, 3} and in {2, 4}, respectively.  2.4. Further generalizations. In this subsection, we give several further generalizations and strengthenings. It includes weighted versions and full cross-intersecting version of our results. All of them we state without proof or with a sketch of proof since the proofs use the same ideas as the proof of Theorems 2.4 and 2.9. Our techniques allow us to give a weighted version of Theorems 2.3 and 2.4. Assume that, given a lower bound on 𝛾(β„±), we aim to maximise the expression βˆ†(β„±) + 𝑐𝛾(β„±) with some 𝑐 > 1. (In terms of cross-intersecting families, we are maximising the expression |π’œ| + 𝑐|ℬ|.) Then the following is true. Theorem 2.10. Let 𝑛 > 2π‘˜ β‰₯ 6. Consider all resistant pairs 𝑆𝑙 βŠ‚ [𝑛], 𝑇𝑙 βŠ‚ [2, 𝑛], where > 1. Then 𝑙 = 0, . . . , π‘š. Assume that 𝑇0 < 𝑇1 < 𝑇2 < . . . < π‘‡π‘š . Put 𝐢 := π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 (2.4)

|β„’(π‘†π‘™βˆ’1 , π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)| + 𝐢|β„’(π‘‡π‘™βˆ’1 , π‘˜)| β‰₯ |β„’(𝑆𝑙 , π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)| + 𝐢|β„’(𝑇𝑙 , π‘˜)|

for each 𝑙 ∈ [π‘š],

(οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€[2,𝑛])οΈ€ and any cross-intersecting pair of families π’œ βŠ‚ [2,𝑛] , ℬ βŠ‚ with |β„’(π‘‡π‘™βˆ’1 , π‘˜)| < |ℬ| ≀ π‘˜βˆ’1 π‘˜ |β„’(𝑇𝑙 , π‘˜)| satisfies |π’œ| + 𝐢|ℬ| ≀ |β„’(𝑆𝑙 , π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)| + 𝐢|β„’(𝑇𝑙 , π‘˜)|. (οΈ€ )οΈ€ In terms of intersecting families, if β„± βŠ‚ [𝑛] is intersecting and |β„’(π‘‡π‘™βˆ’1 , π‘˜)| < 𝛾(β„±) ≀ π‘˜ |β„’(𝑇𝑙 , π‘˜)|, then βˆ†(β„±) + 𝐢𝛾(β„±) ≀ |β„’(𝑆𝑙 , π‘˜ βˆ’ 1)| + 𝐢|β„’(𝑇𝑙 , π‘˜)|. Sketch of the proof. The proof of this theorem follows the same steps as that of Theorem 2.4. We sketch the proof of the cross-intersecting version of the theorem. Using Lemma 2.7, we may assume that π’œ and ℬ form a resistant pair (indeed, otherwise, replacing π’œ, ℬ with π’œβ€² , ℬ β€² which satisfy |π’œβ€² | + |ℬ β€² | β‰₯ |π’œ| + |ℬ|, |ℬ β€² | > |ℬ| definitely increases the value of |π’œ| + 𝐢|ℬ|). Then, looking at the(οΈ€proof )οΈ€ of Lemma (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘–)οΈ€ 2.8, we see that in each of the cases the bipartite graph 𝐺 had parts of sizes π‘›βˆ’π‘– and , where π‘§π‘Ž + 𝑧𝑏 = 2π‘˜ βˆ’ 𝑖 and π‘§π‘Ž > 𝑧𝑏 . Since 𝑖 β‰₯ 5, we have π‘§π‘Ž 𝑧𝑏 (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘–)οΈ€ 𝑧𝑏 ≀ π‘˜ βˆ’ 3. Therefore, if we put weight 𝑀, 𝑀 ≀ π‘›βˆ’π‘– / 𝑧𝑏 , on each vertex of the part 𝒫𝑏 π‘§π‘Ž and weight 1 on each vertex of the part π’«π‘Ž , we can still conclude that π’«π‘Ž is the independent set of the largest weight in 𝐺. The rest of the argument works out as before. We have (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘–)οΈ€ (𝑛 βˆ’ 𝑖 βˆ’ 𝑧𝑏 ) (𝑛 βˆ’ 2π‘˜ + π‘§π‘Ž ) (𝑛 βˆ’ 2π‘˜ + 𝑧𝑏 + 1) (𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜ βˆ’ 2) π‘§π‘Ž (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘– )οΈ€ β‰₯ (2.5) = β‰₯ β‰₯ . 𝑧𝑏 + 1 𝑧𝑏 + 1 𝑧𝑏 + 1 π‘˜βˆ’2 𝑧 𝑏

π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2

as the weight of the vertices in 𝒫𝑏 .  (οΈ€[𝑛])οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’4)οΈ€ Corollary 2.11. Let 𝑛 > 2π‘˜ β‰₯ 6. For any intersecting family β„± βŠ‚ π‘˜ , 𝛾(β„±) ≀ π‘˜βˆ’3 , we (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’1)οΈ€ 𝛾(β„±) ≀ . have |βˆ†(β„±)| + π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’1 (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’1)οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1)οΈ€ π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 If, additionally, β„± is non-trivial, then |βˆ†(β„±)| + π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 𝛾(β„±) ≀ βˆ’ π‘˜βˆ’1 + π‘˜βˆ’2 . π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’1 Therefore, we may use 𝑀 =

Is not difficult (οΈ€[𝑛])οΈ€to extend (οΈ€[𝑛])οΈ€ the considerations of Section 2 to the case of cross-intersecting families π’œ βŠ‚ π‘Ž , ℬ βŠ‚ 𝑏 . The wording of Theorem 2.4 would stay practically the same. One just need to adjust Definition 2. Note that, unlike before in this section, here we will work with cross-intersecting families on [𝑛] (and not [2, 𝑛]), and so β„’(𝑆, π‘Ž) stands for β„’([𝑛], 𝑆, π‘Ž). Definition 4. We say that two sets 𝑆, 𝑇 βŠ‚ [𝑛] form an (π‘Ž, 𝑏)-resistant pair, if either 𝑆 = {𝑏 βˆ’ π‘Ž + 2}, 𝑇 = [𝑏 βˆ’ π‘Ž + 2] or the following holds. Assuming that the largest element of 𝑇 is 𝑗, we have (1) 𝑆 ∩ 𝑇 = {𝑗}, 𝑆 βˆͺ 𝑇 = [𝑗], |𝑆| ≀ π‘Ž and |𝑇 | ≀ 𝑏; (2) for each 𝑖 β‰₯ 𝑏 βˆ’ π‘Ž + 2 we have |[𝑖] ∩ 𝑆| βˆ’ π‘Ž < |[𝑖] βˆ– 𝑆| βˆ’ 𝑏. Let π‘š be the number of resistant pairs. For convenience, put 𝑇0 = [2, 𝑛] to correspond to the empty family, as well as π‘‡π‘š+1 = [𝑏 βˆ’ π‘Ž + 1] and π‘‡π‘š+2 to be the analogues of the sets {2, 3} and {2, 4}, respectively. Below we state a theorem, which is the analogue of Theorems 2.4, 2.9, 2.10 and (the second part of) Corollary 1.4 in the case of general crossintersecting families. Its proof is a straightforward generalization of the proofs of the respective theorems, and thus we omit it. Theorem 2.12. Let 𝑏, π‘Ž > 0, 𝑛 > π‘Ž + 𝑏. Consider all (π‘Ž, 𝑏)-resistant pairs 𝑆𝑙 βŠ‚ [𝑛], 𝑇𝑙 βŠ‚ [2, 𝑛], where 𝑙 ∈ [π‘š]. Assume that 𝑇0 < 𝑇1 < 𝑇2 < . . . π‘‡π‘š . 1. Then |β„’(π‘†π‘™βˆ’1 , π‘Ž)| + |β„’(π‘‡π‘™βˆ’1 , 𝑏)| > |β„’(𝑆𝑙 , π‘Ž)| + |β„’(𝑇𝑙 , 𝑏)| for each 𝑙 ∈ [π‘š], (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€ )οΈ€ and any cross-intersecting pair of families π’œ βŠ‚ [𝑛] , ℬ βŠ‚ [𝑛] with |β„’(π‘‡π‘™βˆ’1 , 𝑏)| < |ℬ| ≀ π‘Ž 𝑏 |β„’(𝑇𝑙 , 𝑏)| satisfies (2.6)

(2.7)

|π’œ| + |ℬ| ≀ |β„’(𝑆𝑙 , π‘Ž)| + |β„’(𝑇𝑙 , 𝑏)|.

If the families β„’(|π’œ|, π‘Ž), β„’(|ℬ|, 𝑏) have characteristic sets 𝑆, 𝑇 , then we have equality in (2.7) if and only if 𝑆, 𝑇 is a 𝑇𝑙 -neutral (π‘Ž, 𝑏)-pair, where the notion of a 𝑇𝑙 -neutral (π‘Ž, 𝑏)-pair is a straightforward generalization of that of neutral pair.

2. The same conclusion holds with |ℬ|, |β„’(π‘‡π‘™βˆ’1 , 𝑏)| |β„’(𝑇𝑙 , 𝑏)| replaced with 𝐢|ℬ|, 𝐢|β„’(π‘‡π‘™βˆ’1 , 𝑏)| . and 𝐢|β„’(𝑇𝑙 , 𝑏)|, where 𝐢 is a constant, 𝐢 < π‘›βˆ’π‘βˆ’1 (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘–)οΈ€ π‘Žβˆ’1 (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘‘)οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘‘βˆ’1)οΈ€ 3. Denote 𝑑 := 𝑏+1βˆ’π‘Ž. Assume that π‘βˆ’π‘– < |ℬ| ≀ π‘Žβˆ’1 + π‘Žβˆ’1 for integer 𝑖 ∈ [𝑑+1, 𝑏]. If 𝑖 β‰₯ 𝑑 + 2 then we have (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ 𝑛 π‘›βˆ’π‘– π‘›βˆ’π‘– π‘›βˆ’π‘βˆ’1 |π’œ| + |ℬ| ≀ βˆ’ + βˆ’ + 1. π‘Ž π‘Ž π‘βˆ’π‘– π‘Žβˆ’1

If 𝑖 = 𝑑 + 1 and |ℬ| ∈ /[ we have

(οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘‘)οΈ€ π‘Žβˆ’1

βˆ’

(οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘βˆ’1)οΈ€ π‘Žβˆ’1

+ 2,

(οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘‘)οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘‘)οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘‘βˆ’1)οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘βˆ’1)οΈ€ ], |ℬ| ≀ + π‘Žβˆ’1 βˆ’ π‘Žβˆ’1 + 1 then π‘Žβˆ’1 π‘Žβˆ’1

(οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ 𝑛 π‘›βˆ’π‘‘ π‘›βˆ’π‘‘ π‘›βˆ’π‘βˆ’1 |π’œ| + |ℬ| ≀ βˆ’ + βˆ’ + 1. π‘Ž π‘Ž π‘βˆ’π‘‘ π‘Žβˆ’1

(οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘‘)οΈ€ Remark that we have |π’œ| + |ℬ| = π‘›π‘Ž βˆ’ π‘›βˆ’π‘‘ + π‘Žβˆ’1 for π’œ, ℬ defined by characteristic sets π‘Ž 𝑆𝑖 , 𝑇𝑖 , where 𝑖 = π‘š, π‘š + 1, π‘š + 2. This theorem generalizes and strengthens many results on cross-intersecting families, in particular, the theorem for cross-intersecting families proven in [43] and the following theorem due to Frankl and Tokushige [25] Theorem Tokushige, [25]). Let 𝑛 > π‘Ž + 𝑏, π‘Ž ≀ 𝑏, and suppose that families (οΈ€[𝑛])οΈ€ 2.13 (οΈ€[𝑛](Frankl, )οΈ€ β„± βŠ‚ , 𝒒 βŠ‚ are cross-intersecting. Suppose that for some real number 𝛼 β‰₯ 1 we have 𝑏 )οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π›Ό)οΈ€ π‘Ž (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’1 ≀ |β„±| ≀ π‘›βˆ’π‘Ž . Then π‘›βˆ’π‘Ž (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ 𝑛 π‘›βˆ’π›Ό π‘›βˆ’π›Ό (2.8) |β„±| + |𝒒| ≀ + βˆ’ . 𝑏 π‘›βˆ’π‘Ž 𝑏 One easy corollary of (2.6) and (2.7), which also appeared in [43] and other places, is as follows: (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€ )οΈ€ Corollary 2.14 ([43]). Let π‘Ž, 𝑏 > 0, 𝑛 > π‘Ž + 𝑏. Let π’œ βŠ‚ [𝑛] , ℬ βŠ‚ [𝑛] be a pair of π‘Ž(οΈ€ 𝑏 )οΈ€ π‘›βˆ’π‘‘ cross-intersecting families. Denote 𝑑 := 𝑏 + 1 βˆ’ π‘Ž. Then, if |ℬ| ≀ π‘Žβˆ’1 , then (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ 𝑛 (2.9) |π’œ| + |ℬ| ≀ . π‘Ž Moreover, (οΈ€ )οΈ€ the displayed (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘‘)οΈ€ inequality is strict unless |ℬ| = 0. If π‘›βˆ’π‘— ≀ |ℬ| ≀ for integer 𝑗 ∈ [𝑑, 𝑏], then π‘βˆ’π‘— π‘Žβˆ’1 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ 𝑛 π‘›βˆ’π‘— π‘›βˆ’π‘— (2.10) |π’œ| + |ℬ| ≀ βˆ’ + . π‘Ž π‘Ž π‘βˆ’π‘— Moreover, if the left inequality on ℬ is strict, (οΈ€then)οΈ€ the inequality in the displayed formula π‘›βˆ’π‘‘ above is also strict, unless 𝑗 = 𝑑 + 1 and |ℬ| = π‘Žβˆ’1 . We note that the results in [43] did not explicitly treat the equality case. However, it is clear that strictness of (2.9) follows from (2.10), and the equality case in (2.10) follows from Theorem 2.12 part 3. 3. Beyond Hilton–Milner. Proofs of Theorem 1.5 and 1.7 Proof of Theorem 1.5. As we have already mentioned in the introduction, applying Corollary 1.4 with 𝑒 = π‘˜, we conclude that (1.4) holds for π‘˜ β‰₯ 4. Next, in terms of Theorem 2.3, we know that 𝛾𝑖 = 𝑖 for 𝑖 ∈ [π‘˜ βˆ’ 3], and π›Ύπ‘˜βˆ’2 = 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜. Thus,(οΈ€ for )οΈ€ π‘˜ β‰₯ 5, 𝛾2 = 2 and, using Theorem 2.3, we conclude that any intersecting family β„± βŠ‚ [𝑛] with 𝛾(β„±) β‰₯ 3 is strictly smaller than the right hand side of (1.4). Therefore, if β„± π‘˜ with 𝛾(β„±) β‰₯ 2 has size equal to the right hand side of (1.4), then 𝛾(β„±) = 2. But then any maximal β„± must be isomorphic to π’₯𝑖 for some 𝑖 β‰₯ 2 (since the family is uniquely determined by the size of the intersection of the two sets contributing to the diversity). Finally, as we have mentioned in the introduction, |π’₯𝑖 | < |π’₯2 | for any 𝑖 > 2. 

Let us recall the definition of shifting. For a given pair of indices 1 ≀ 𝑖 < 𝑗 ≀ 𝑛 and a set 𝐴 βŠ‚ [𝑛], define its (𝑖, 𝑗)-shift 𝑆𝑖𝑗 (𝐴) as follows. If 𝑖 ∈ 𝐴 or 𝑗 ∈ / 𝐴, then 𝑆𝑖𝑗 (𝐴) = 𝐴. If 𝑗 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑖 ∈ / 𝐴, then 𝑆𝑖𝑗 (𝐴) := (𝐴 βˆ’ {𝑗}) βˆͺ {𝑖}. That is, 𝑆𝑖𝑗 (𝐴) is obtained from 𝐴 by replacing 𝑗 with 𝑖. The (𝑖, 𝑗)-shift 𝑆𝑖𝑗 (π’œ) of a family π’œ is as follows: 𝑆𝑖𝑗 (π’œ) := {𝑆𝑖𝑗 (𝐴) : 𝐴 ∈ π’œ} βˆͺ {𝐴 : 𝐴, 𝑆𝑖𝑗 (𝐴) ∈ π’œ}. 3.1. Proof of Theorem 1.7. Let us deal with the first part of the statement first. Assume that the statement does not hold and choose β„±, 𝑑, β„³, and β„± β€² satisfying the requirements of the theorem, so that |β„±| > |β„± β€² | and β„± has the smallest (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’4)οΈ€ possible diversity under these conditions. First, we can clearly suppose that 𝛾(β„±) ≀ π‘˜βˆ’3 . Indeed, the largest family with (οΈ€ )οΈ€ diversity bigger than π‘›βˆ’4 is at most as large as β„‹4 (cf. (1.1)), and β„‹4 contains a copy of π‘˜βˆ’3 any 𝒒 as in the statement of the theorem. Therefore, by the choice of β„±, it cannot have diversity larger than β„‹4 , otherwise we should with β„‹4 . (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’4)οΈ€have replaced β„± β‹‚οΈ€ From now on, we suppose that 𝛾(β„±) ≀ π‘˜βˆ’3 . Suppose that 𝑀 βˆˆβ„³ 𝑀 = [2, 𝑑 + 1]. For 𝑖 = 2, . . . , 𝑑 + 1, we may consecutively apply all the 𝑆𝑖𝑗 -shifts, where 𝑗 > 𝑖, to β„±. Note that the family β„³ stays intact under these shifts, and the diversity and size of β„± is not affected. Thus, we may assume that β„± is invariant under these shifts. For any 𝑗 β‰₯ 2 and 𝑆 βŠ‚ [2, 𝑗], define {οΈ€ }οΈ€ β„±(𝑆, [𝑗]) := 𝐹 βŠ‚ [𝑗 + 1, 𝑛] : 𝐹 βˆͺ 𝑆 ∈ β„±(Β―1) (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€ 𝑅 )οΈ€ ⋃︀ and, for any family β„› βŠ‚ [𝑛] , let πœ•β„› := π‘…βˆˆβ„› π‘˜βˆ’1 denote the shadow of β„›. (We gave an π‘˜ equivalent definition in Theorem 2.2.) An important consequence of the shifts we made is that, for any 𝑖 ∈ [2, 𝑑 + 1] and 𝑆 βŠ‚ [2, 𝑖 βˆ’ 1], we have βƒ’ βƒ’ βƒ’ βƒ’ βƒ’β„±(𝑆 βˆͺ {𝑖}, [𝑖])βƒ’ β‰₯ βƒ’πœ•β„±(𝑆, [𝑖])βƒ’. (3.1) Actually, we have β„±(𝑆 βˆͺ {𝑖}, [𝑖]) βŠƒ πœ•β„±(𝑆, [𝑖]). Indeed, for any 𝐹 β€² ∈ πœ•β„±(𝑆, [𝑖]), there exists 𝑗 ∈ [𝑖 + 1, 𝑛] and 𝐹 ∈ β„±(𝑆, [𝑖]), such that 𝐹 β€² βˆͺ {𝑗} = 𝐹 , and, since we the (𝑖, 𝑗)–shift, we β€² have 𝐹 β€² βˆͺ {𝑖} βˆͺ 𝑆 ∈ β„± and (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’4 )οΈ€ 𝐹 ∈ β„±(𝑆 βˆͺ {𝑖}, [𝑖]). We have |β„±(Β―1)| ≀ π‘˜βˆ’3 by assumption. Let us show that, for any 𝑖 ∈ [2, 4], we have (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘›βˆ’5 (3.2) |β„±([2, 𝑖 βˆ’ 1], [𝑖])| ≀ . π‘˜βˆ’3 (Naturally, we put [2, 1] = βˆ….) Assume that (3.2) does not hold. Then, (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’5)οΈ€ 7using the Kruskal– Katona theorem, it is not difficult to see that |πœ•β„±([2, 𝑖 βˆ’ 1], [𝑖])| > π‘˜βˆ’4 , and thus (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ βƒ’ βƒ’ βƒ’ βƒ’ βƒ’ βƒ’ (3.1) βƒ’ βƒ’ βƒ’ βƒ’ βƒ’β„±(Β―1)βƒ’ β‰₯ βƒ’β„±([2, π‘–βˆ’1], [𝑖])βƒ’ + βƒ’β„±([2, 𝑖], [𝑖])βƒ’ β‰₯ βƒ’β„±([2, π‘–βˆ’1], [𝑖])βƒ’ + βƒ’πœ•β„±([2, π‘–βˆ’1], [𝑖])βƒ’ > 𝑛 βˆ’ 4 , π‘˜βˆ’3 a contradiction. For each 𝑖 ∈ [2, 4], consider the following bipartite graph 𝐺𝑖 . The parts of 𝐺𝑖 are (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {︁ [2, 𝑛] }︁ , π’«π‘Ž (𝑖) := 𝑃 : 𝑖 ∈ 𝑃 ∈ π‘˜βˆ’1 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {︁ [2, 𝑛] }︁ 𝒫𝑏 (𝑖) := 𝑃 : 𝑖 ∈ /𝑃 ∈ , π‘˜ (οΈ€ 𝑋 )οΈ€ (οΈ€ )οΈ€ and edges connect disjoint sets. We identify π’«π‘Ž (𝑖) with π‘˜βˆ’2 and 𝒫𝑏 (𝑖) with π‘‹π‘˜ , where 𝑋 := [2, 𝑛] βˆ– {𝑖}, |𝑋| = 𝑛 βˆ’ 2 > π‘˜ + π‘˜ βˆ’ 2. 7Assume

that we have equality in (3.2). The Kruskal–Katona theorem that if 𝒦 (οΈ€ π‘₯ )οΈ€ in Lovasz’ form (οΈ€ π‘₯ states )οΈ€ a family of π‘š-element sets and, for some real π‘₯ β‰₯ π‘š, we have |𝒦| β‰₯ π‘š , then |πœ•π’¦| β‰₯ π‘šβˆ’1 . In our case, (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’5)οΈ€ (οΈ€ π‘₯ )οΈ€ 𝒦 := β„±([2, 𝑖 βˆ’ 1], [𝑖]) βŠ‚ [𝑖+1,𝑛] π‘˜βˆ’π‘–+1 and π‘˜βˆ’3 = π‘˜βˆ’π‘–+1 , where π‘₯ ≀ 𝑛 βˆ’ 5 for any 𝑖 ∈ [2, 4]. Finally, we have π‘₯ (οΈ€ π‘₯ )οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’5)οΈ€ (π‘˜βˆ’π‘–+1 ) (π‘›βˆ’5 π‘˜βˆ’3 ) = π‘₯βˆ’π‘˜+𝑖 ≀ π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 = π‘›βˆ’5 , and thus |πœ•π’¦| > π‘˜βˆ’π‘– β‰₯ π‘˜βˆ’4 . π‘₯ π‘˜βˆ’π‘–+1 π‘˜βˆ’3 (π‘˜βˆ’π‘–) (π‘˜βˆ’4)

Due to (3.2), we have |𝒫𝑏 (𝑖) ∩ β„±(Β―1)| ≀ (2.9) to

(οΈ€π‘›βˆ’5)οΈ€ π‘˜βˆ’3

=

|𝑋|βˆ’3 (π‘˜βˆ’2)βˆ’1

(οΈ€

)οΈ€

for 𝑖 = 2. Thus, we can apply

and ℬ := β„±(Β―1) ∩ 𝒫𝑏 (𝑖), (οΈ€ |𝑋| )οΈ€ where 𝑖 = 2, and conclude that |π’œ| + |ℬ| ≀ π‘˜βˆ’2 (and the inequality is strict unless ℬ = βˆ…). Β― Β― Therefore, removing β„±(1) ∩ 𝒫𝑏 (2) from β„±(1) and adding sets from π’«π‘Ž (2) to β„±(1), we get a pair of families with larger sum of cardinalities. Moreover, the new pair is cross-intersecting: all sets in β„±(Β―1) βˆ– 𝒫𝑏 (2), as well as the sets from π’«π‘Ž (2), contain 2. Thus, by our choice of β„± we may assume that ℬ = βˆ… and so all sets in β„±(Β―1) must contain 2. Repeat this argument for 𝑖 = 3 and 𝑖 = 4. Concluding, we may assume that all sets in β„±(Β―1) contain [2, 4]. Next, for each 𝑖 β‰₯ 5, consider the following slightly different bipartite graph 𝐺′𝑖 . The parts of 𝐺𝑖 are (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {︁ }︁ [2, 𝑛] β€² π’«π‘Ž (𝑖) := 𝑃 : 𝑃 ∈ , 𝑃 ∩ [2, 𝑖] = {𝑖} , π‘˜βˆ’1 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {︁ }︁ [2, 𝑛] β€² 𝒫𝑏 (𝑖) := 𝑃 : 𝑃 ∈ , 𝑃 ∩ [2, 𝑖] = [2, 𝑖 βˆ’ 1] , π‘˜ (οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€ )οΈ€ and edges connect disjoint sets. We identify π’«π‘Žβ€² (𝑖) with [𝑖+1,𝑛] and 𝒫𝑏′ (𝑖) with [𝑖+1,𝑛] . π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’π‘–+1 (οΈ€ π‘›βˆ’π‘– )οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’5)οΈ€ β€² We have |𝒫𝑏 (𝑖) ∩ β„±(Β―1)| ≀ π‘˜βˆ’π‘–+1 ≀ π‘˜βˆ’3 . Thus, for each 𝑖 = 5, . . . , 𝑑 + 1 we can apply (2.9) to π’œ := β„±(1) ∩ π’«π‘Ž (𝑖)

Β― ∩ 𝒫𝑏′ (𝑖), π’œ := β„±(1) ∩ π’«π‘Žβ€² (𝑖) and ℬ := β„±(1) (οΈ€ π‘›βˆ’π‘– )οΈ€ and conclude that |π’œ| + |ℬ| ≀ π‘˜βˆ’2 (and the inequality is strict unless ℬ = βˆ…). Arguing as before, we may assume that all sets in β„±(Β―1) contain [2, 𝑑 + 1]. Put β„³ = {𝑀1 , . . . , 𝑀𝑧 }. Since β„³ is minimal, for each 𝑀𝑙 ∈ β„³, 𝑙 ∈ [𝑧], there is (︁ )︁ (︁ ⋂︁ )︁ ⋂︁ (3.3) 𝑖𝑙 ∈ 𝑀 βˆ– 𝑀 . 𝑀 βˆˆβ„³βˆ–{𝑀𝑙 }

𝑀 βˆˆβ„³

We assume that 𝑖𝑙 = 𝑑 + 𝑙 + 1, 𝑙 ∈ [𝑧]. In particular, {𝑖1 , . . . , 𝑖𝑧 } = [𝑑 + 2, 𝑑 + 𝑧 + 1]. Next, for each 𝑖 = 𝑑 + 2, . . . , 𝑑 + 𝑧 + 1 consider the bipartite graph 𝐺′𝑖 , defined above. We can apply (2.10) with π‘˜ βˆ’ 2,(οΈ€π‘˜ βˆ’ 𝑖 + 1, π‘˜ βˆ’ )︀𝑖 + 1, 4 βˆ’ 𝑖 playing roles of π‘Ž, 𝑏, 𝑗, 𝑑, respectively. π‘›βˆ’π‘– Indeed, we know that |ℬ| β‰₯ (π‘˜βˆ’π‘–+1)βˆ’(π‘˜βˆ’π‘–+1) = 1 since π‘€π‘–βˆ’π‘‘βˆ’1 ∈ 𝒫𝑏′ (𝑖) (note that 𝑀𝑙 ∈ / 𝒫𝑏′ (𝑖) 𝑙)οΈ€ΜΈ= 𝑖 (οΈ€βˆ’ 𝑑 βˆ’ 1, (οΈ€for )οΈ€ since all of them contain 𝑖𝑙 due to the definition of 𝑖𝑙 ). Therefore, |π’œ| + |ℬ| ≀ π‘›βˆ’π‘– π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’π‘– βˆ’ + 1. For π‘˜ β‰₯ 5, the inequality is strict unless ℬ = {π‘€π‘–βˆ’π‘‘βˆ’1 }. For π‘˜ = 4, we π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 apply it for 𝑖 = 4, thus 𝑛 βˆ’ 5, 2,(οΈ€ 1, 1,)οΈ€ 0 play the roles of 𝑛, π‘Ž, 𝑏, 𝑗, 𝑑, respectively, and so the inequality is strict unless |ℬ| = π‘›βˆ’5 , i.e., ℬ contains all possible 1-element sets. Thus, we 1 )οΈ€ (οΈ€ β€² may replace π’œ, ℬ with ℬ := {π‘€π‘–βˆ’π‘‘βˆ’1 } and π’œβ€² := {𝐴 ∈ [𝑖+1,𝑛] : 𝐴 ∩ π‘€π‘–βˆ’π‘‘βˆ’1 ΜΈ= βˆ…}. The π‘˜βˆ’2 resulting family is cross-intersecting. Thus, by our choice of β„±, all sets in β„±(Β―1) βˆ– β„³ must contain 𝑖. Iterating this procedure for 𝑖 = 𝑑 + 2, 𝑑 + 3, . . . , 𝑑 + 𝑧 + 1, we may assume that any set in β„±(Β―1) βˆ– β„³ must contain the set [2, 𝑑 + 𝑧 + 1]. Put 𝑑′ := 𝑑 + 𝑧 + 1. If β„±(Β―1) βˆ– β„³ is non-empty then, for each 𝑙 ∈ [𝑧], the set 𝑀𝑙 βˆ– [2, 𝑑′ ] must be non-empty: otherwise, 𝑑′ βˆ’ 1 > π‘˜. If β„±(Β―1) βˆ– β„³ is empty then β„±(Β―1) = β„³, which contradicts |β„±| > |β„± β€² |. Note that 𝑑′ βˆ’ 1 β‰₯ 𝑧 + 3. For each 𝑙 ∈ [𝑧], select one element 𝑖𝑙 ∈ 𝑀𝑙 ∩ [𝑑′ + 1, 𝑛]. Note that 𝑖𝑙 may coincide. Put 𝐼 := {𝑖𝑙 : 𝑙 ∈ [𝑧]}. Consider the bipartite graph 𝐺(𝑑′ , 𝐼) with parts (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {︁ }︁ [2, 𝑛] β€² π’«π‘Ž (𝑑 , 𝐼) := 𝑃 : 𝑃 ∈ , 𝐼 βŠ‚ 𝑃, [2, 𝑑′ ] ∩ 𝑃 = βˆ… , π‘˜βˆ’1 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {︁ }︁ [2, 𝑛] β€² β€² 𝒫𝑏 (𝑑 , 𝐼) := 𝑃 : 𝑃 ∈ , [2, 𝑑 ] βŠ‚ 𝑃, 𝐼 ∩ 𝑃 = βˆ… , π‘˜

(οΈ€ π‘Œ )οΈ€ β€² β€² and edges connecting disjoint sets. We identify π’«π‘Ž (𝑑′ , 𝐼) with π‘˜βˆ’π‘§ β€² , 𝑧 ≀ 𝑧 + 1, and 𝒫𝑏 (𝑑 , 𝐼) (οΈ€ π‘Œ )οΈ€ β€²β€² with π‘˜βˆ’π‘§β€²β€² , 𝑧 = 𝑑′ βˆ’ 1 β‰₯ 𝑧 + 3, where π‘Œ = [𝑑′ + 1, 𝑛] βˆ– 𝐼, |π‘Œ | = 𝑛 βˆ’ 𝑧 β€²β€² βˆ’ 𝑧 β€² . In particular, |π‘Œ | > π‘˜ βˆ’ 𝑧 β€² + π‘˜ βˆ’ 𝑧 β€²β€² . By the choice of 𝐼, we have |β„³ ∩ 𝒫𝑏 (𝑑′ , 𝐼)| = βˆ…. Denote Β― ∩ 𝒫𝑏 (𝑑′ , 𝐼). π’œ := β„±(1) ∩ π’«π‘Ž (𝑑′ , 𝐼) and ℬ := β„±(1) We have π‘˜ βˆ’ 𝑧 β€² > π‘˜ βˆ’ 𝑧 β€²β€² , and, therefore, we may apply (2.9) with π‘Ž := π‘˜ βˆ’ 𝑧 β€² , 𝑏 := π‘˜ βˆ’ 𝑧 β€²β€² , 𝑗 := π‘˜ βˆ’(︀𝑧 β€²β€² (the upper bound on |ℬ| becomes trivial in that case) and conclude )οΈ€ |π‘Œ | that |π’œ| + |ℬ| ≀ π‘˜βˆ’π‘§β€² (and the inequality is strict unless ℬ = βˆ…). As before, replacing π’œ with π’«π‘Ž (𝐼) and ℬ with βˆ… does not decrease the sum of sizes of the families and preserves the cross-intersecting property. Thus, by the choice of β„±, we must have ℬ = βˆ…. Repeating this for all possible choices of 𝐼, we arrive at the situation when any set from β„±(Β―1) βˆ– β„³ must intersect any such set 𝐼. Clearly, this is only possible for a set 𝐹 if 𝐹 βŠƒ 𝑀𝑙 ∩ [𝑑′ + 1, 𝑛]. But this implies that |𝐹 | > |𝑀𝑙 |, which is impossible. Thus β„±(Β―1) = β„³, which contradicts |β„±| > |β„± β€² |, so the proof of (1.5) is complete. Finally, uniqueness follows from the fact that the inequalities (2.9), (2.10) are strict unless the family ℬ has sizes 0 and 1, respectively, or π‘˜ = 4 (we mentioned it at every application). Therefore, if β„±(Β―1) ΜΈ= β„³, then at some point we would have had a strict inequality in the application of (2.9), (2.10). Let us now prove the moreover part of the statement of Theorem 1.7. First, if there is β‹‚οΈ€ no family β„³ βŠ‚ β„±(Β―1), minimal w.r.t. common intersection and such that | 𝑀 βˆˆβ„³ 𝑀 | = 𝑑, then we apply (𝑖, 𝑗)-shifts to β„± for 2 ≀ 𝑖 < 𝑗 ≀ 𝑛 until such family appears. Since common intersection of any subfamily of β„±(Β―1) may change by at most one after any shift, either we obtain the desired β„³ or we arrive at a shifted family β„±(Β―1) without such β‹‚οΈ€ β„³. But the latter is impossible. Indeed, for a shifted intersecting family β„±(Β―1), we have | 𝐹 βˆˆβ„± (Β―1) 𝐹 | = [2, 𝑗] for some 𝑗 β‰₯ 2, and in that case [2, 𝑗] βˆͺ [𝑗 + 2, π‘˜ + 2] ∈ β„±(Β―1). But then the set 𝐹𝑗 β€² := [2 + 𝑗 β€² ] βˆͺ [𝑗 β€² + 2, π‘˜ + 2] ∈ β„±(Β―1), where 𝑗 ≀ 𝑗 β€² ≀ π‘˜ + 1. It is clear that the sets 𝐹𝑗 , . . . , πΉπ‘˜βˆ’π‘‘+𝑗+1 form a subfamily that has common intersection of size 𝑑. β‹‚οΈ€ Fix β„³ βŠ‚ β„±(Β―1), minimal w.r.t. common intersection, such that | 𝑀 βˆˆβ„³ 𝑀 | = 𝑑. Applying Β― the first part of Theorem β‹‚οΈ€ 2.4, we may assume that β„±(1) = β„³. Clearly, the number of sets in of the form of β„³. }οΈ€ Thus, β„±(1) passing through 𝑀 βˆˆβ„³ 𝑀 is always the same, independently {οΈ€ β‹‚οΈ€ we need{οΈ€to analyze the sum of sizes }οΈ€of the family β„± β€² := 𝐹 ∈ β„±(1) : 𝐹 ∩ 𝑀 βˆˆβ„³ 𝑀 = βˆ… and β‹‚οΈ€ β„³β€² := 𝑀 βˆ– 𝑀 βˆˆβ„³ 𝑀 : 𝑀 ∈ β„³ . Note that β„³β€² and β„± β€² are cross-intersecting, moreover, 𝜏 (β„³β€² ) = 2 and β„³β€² is minimal w.r.t. this property. The following lemma concludes the proof of the theorem. Let us first give some (οΈ€definitions. )οΈ€ [π‘š] stand Given integers π‘š > 2𝑠, let us denote by 𝒯2β€² (𝑠) := {[𝑠], [𝑠 + 1, 2𝑠]}. Let β„±2β€² (𝑠) βŠ‚ π‘˜βˆ’1 (οΈ€ [π‘š] )οΈ€ β€² for the largest family, cross-intersecting with 𝒯2 (𝑠). Let β„±2 (𝑠) βŠ‚ π‘˜βˆ’1 stand for the largest family, cross-intersecting with 𝒯2 (𝑠) (cf. (1.7)). (οΈ€ )οΈ€ Lemma 3.1. Let π‘˜ β‰₯ 𝑠 and π‘š β‰₯ π‘˜ + 𝑠 be integers, π‘˜ β‰₯ 4. Given a family β„‹ βŠ‚ [π‘š] with (οΈ€ [π‘š] )︀𝑠 𝜏 (β„‹) = 2 and minimal w.r.t. this property, consider the maximal family β„± βŠ‚ π‘˜βˆ’1 that is cross-intersecting with β„‹. Then the unique maximum of |β„±| + |β„‹| is attained when β„‹ is isomorphic to 𝒯2β€² (𝑠) (and β„± is thus isomorphic to β„±2β€² (𝑠)). If we additionally require that β„‹ is intersecting8 then the maximum of |β„±| + |β„‹| is attained for β„‹ and β„± isomorphic to 𝒯2 (𝑠) and β„±2 (𝑠). The maximal configuration is unique if 𝑠 β‰₯ π‘˜. β‹‚οΈ€ We can apply the first part of Lemma 3.1 in our situation with [2, 𝑛]βˆ– 𝑀 βˆˆβ„³ 𝑀 playing the β‹‚οΈ€ role of [π‘š] and π‘˜ βˆ’ 𝑑 playing the role of 𝑠. Note that |[2, 𝑛] βˆ– 𝑀 βˆˆβ„³ 𝑀 | = 𝑛 βˆ’ 𝑑 βˆ’ 1 β‰₯ 2π‘˜ βˆ’ 𝑑, and so the condition on π‘š from the lemma is satisfied. This proves (1.6), moreover, we get that for π‘˜ β‰₯ 5 the inequality was strict unless |β„±(Β―1)| = 2 in the first place. But then β„± is 8Note

that this is equivalent to requiring that |β„‹| > 2.

isomorphic to a subfamily of π’₯𝑖 for 𝑖 β‰₯ 𝑖′ , and the equality is possible only if β„± is isomorphic to π’₯𝑖 . Thus, to conclude the proof of Theorem 2.4, we only have to prove the lemma. We note that the second, more complicated, part of Lemmaβ€˜3.1 is not needed for this application, however, it will be crucial for the completion of the proof of Theorem 1.10. Proof of Lemma 3.1. Let us first express |β„±2β€² (𝑠)|. It is not difficult to see that |β„±2β€² (𝑠)|

(3.4)

(οΈ‚

)οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘šβˆ’1 π‘šβˆ’π‘ βˆ’1 = βˆ’ + π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘šβˆ’2 π‘šβˆ’π‘ βˆ’2 βˆ’ + π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 Β·Β·Β· (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘šβˆ’π‘  π‘š βˆ’ 2𝑠 βˆ’ . π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2

Indeed, in the first line we count the sets containing 1 that intersect [𝑠 + 1, 2𝑠], in the second line we count the sets not containing 1, containing 2 and intersecting [𝑠 + 1, 2𝑠] etc. We can actually bound the size of β„± for any β„‹ in a similar way. Suppose that 𝑧 := |β„‹| and β„‹ = {𝐻1 , . . . , 𝐻𝑧 }.β‹‚οΈ€ Since β„‹ is minimal, for each 𝑙 ∈ [𝑧] there exists an element 𝑖𝑙 such that 𝑖𝑙 ∈ / 𝐻𝑙 and 𝑖𝑙 ∈ π‘—βˆˆ[𝑧]βˆ–{𝑙} 𝐻𝑙 . (All 𝑖𝑙 are of course different, cf. also (3.3).) Applying (οΈ€ )οΈ€ Bollobas’ set-pairs inequality [3] to β„‹ and {𝑖𝑙 : 𝑙 ∈ [𝑧]}, we get that |β„‹| ≀ 𝑠+1 = 𝑠 + 1. 𝑠 For each 𝑙 = 2, . . . , 𝑧, we count the sets 𝐹 ∈ β„± such that 𝐹 ∩ {𝑖2 , . . . , 𝑖𝑙 } = {𝑖𝑙 }. Such sets must additionally intersect 𝐻𝑙 βˆ– {𝑖2 , . . . , π‘–π‘™βˆ’1 }. Note that 𝐻1 βŠƒ {𝑖2 , . . . , 𝑖𝑧 }. Assuming that 𝐻1 βˆ– {𝑖2 , . . . , 𝑖𝑧 } = {𝑗1 , . . . , π‘—π‘ βˆ’π‘§ }, for each 𝑙 = 1, . . . , 𝑠 βˆ’ 𝑧 we further count the sets 𝐹 ∈ β„± such that 𝐹 ∩ {𝑖2 , . . . , 𝑖𝑧 , 𝑗1 , . . . , 𝑗𝑙 } = {𝑗𝑙 }. Such sets must additionally intersect 𝐻𝑖 βˆ– {𝑖2 , . . . , 𝑖𝑧 } for some 𝑖 ∈ [2, 𝑧].9 Since 𝐹 ∩ 𝐻1 ΜΈ= βˆ… for any 𝐹 ∈ β„± and given that the classes for different 𝑙 are disjoint, we clearly counted each set from β„± exactly once. (However, we may also count some sets that are not in β„±.) Doing this count, we get the following bound on β„±. (οΈ‚

(3.5)

)οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘šβˆ’1 π‘šβˆ’π‘ βˆ’1 |β„±| ≀ βˆ’ + π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘šβˆ’2 π‘šβˆ’π‘ βˆ’1 βˆ’ + π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 Β·Β·Β· (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘šβˆ’π‘§+1 π‘šβˆ’π‘ βˆ’1 βˆ’ + π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘šβˆ’π‘§ π‘šβˆ’π‘ βˆ’2 βˆ’ + π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 Β·Β·Β· (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘šβˆ’π‘  π‘š βˆ’ 2𝑠 βˆ’ 2 + 𝑧 βˆ’ =: 𝑓 (𝑧). π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2

(3.8) (οΈ€Remark )οΈ€ that (οΈ€π‘šβˆ’π‘ βˆ’2 )οΈ€ coincides (οΈ€π‘šβˆ’π‘ βˆ’2)οΈ€with (3.4) when substituting 𝑧 = 2. We have 𝑓 (𝑧 βˆ’ 1) βˆ’ 𝑓 (𝑧) β‰₯ π‘šβˆ’π‘ βˆ’1 βˆ’ π‘˜βˆ’2 = π‘˜βˆ’3 > 1 (here we use that π‘š β‰₯ 𝑠 + π‘˜ and π‘˜ β‰₯ 4). Therefore, for π‘˜βˆ’2 any 𝑧 β‰₯ 𝑧 β€² , (3.6)

|β„‹| + |β„±| ≀ 𝑓 (𝑧 β€² ) + 𝑧 β€² ,

and the inequality is strict unless 𝑧 = |β„‹| = 𝑧 β€² . At the same time, we have |β„±2β€² (𝑠)| + |𝒯2β€² (𝑠)| = 𝑓 (2) + 2 and |β„±2 (𝑠)| + |𝒯2 (𝑠)| = 𝑓 (3) + 3! (The former we have seen above, and the latter is easy to verify by (οΈ€[π‘š] )οΈ€ doing exactly the same count.) Since, up to isomorphism, there is only one family β„‹ βŠ‚ 𝑠 of size 2 with 𝜏 (β„‹) = 2, we immediately conclude that the first part of the statement holds. To deduce the second 9Otherwise,

β„‹ would have common intersection. Note that 𝐻𝑖 βˆ– {𝑖2 , . . . , 𝑖𝑧 } is a set of size 𝑠 βˆ’ 𝑧 + 2.

part, we only need to show that, among all possible choices of β„‹ of size 3, the only one (up to isomorphism) that attains equality in (3.6) is β„‹ = 𝒯2 (𝑠). Recall that, for uniqueness in the second part of the lemma, we have additional condition 𝑠 β‰₯ π‘˜. If there are two sets 𝐻 β€² , 𝐻 β€²β€² ∈ β„‹ such that |𝐻 β€² ∩ 𝐻 β€²β€² | = 𝑠 βˆ’ 1, then β„‹ is isomorphic to 𝒯2 (𝑠). Therefore, in what follows we assume that |𝐻 β€² ∩ 𝐻 β€²β€² | ≀ 𝑠 βˆ’ 2 for any 𝐻 β€² , 𝐻 β€²β€² ∈ β„‹. Let us deal with the case when 𝐻𝑙 ∩ 𝐻𝑙′ = 𝑖𝑙′′ for any {𝑙, 𝑙′ , 𝑙′′ } = [3]. Note that this implies that (3.7)

π‘š β‰₯ 3𝑠 βˆ’ 3.

Since 𝑠 β‰₯ π‘˜ β‰₯ 4, there are elements 𝑗𝑙 ∈ 𝐻𝑙 βˆ– (𝐻𝑙′ βˆͺ 𝐻𝑙′′ ), {𝑙, 𝑙′ , 𝑙′′ } = [3]. Perform the (𝑗1 , 𝑗2 )shift on β„± βˆͺ β„‹ and denote β„± β€² := 𝑆𝑗1 𝑗2 (β„±). Clearly, the sizes of the families stay the same and the resulting families are cross-intersecting. The family, 𝑆𝑗1 𝑗2 (β„‹) has covering number 2. Moreover, we can add new sets to β„± β€² without violating the cross-intersecting property. Indeed, consider the families (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {︁ }︁ [π‘š] π’œ := 𝐹 ∈ : 𝑗3 ∈ 𝐹, 𝐹 ∩ (𝐻1 βˆͺ 𝐻2 ) = {𝑗2 } , π‘˜βˆ’1 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ {︁ }︁ [π‘š] β€² π’œ := 𝐹 ∈ : 𝑗3 ∈ 𝐹, 𝐹 ∩ (𝐻1 βˆͺ 𝐻2 ) = {𝑗1 } . π‘˜βˆ’1 It is easy to see that actually π’œβ€² = 𝑆𝑗1 𝑗2 (π’œ). Moreover, π’œ ∩ β„± = βˆ… since sets from π’œ do not intersect 𝐻1 and π’œβ€² ∩ β„± β€² = βˆ… since π’œβ€² ∩ β„± = βˆ… (again, since sets from π’œβ€² do not intersect 𝐻2 ) and π’œ ∩ β„± = βˆ…. At the same time, (οΈ€π’œβ€² may be included into β„± β€² since sets from(οΈ€π’œβ€² )οΈ€intersect )οΈ€ all sets in 𝑆𝑗1 𝑗2 (β„‹). Finally, π’œ = [π‘š]βˆ–π‘‹ , where |𝑋| = 2𝑠, and thus |π’œ| β‰₯ π‘˜βˆ’3 due to π‘˜βˆ’3 π‘˜βˆ’3 π‘š β‰₯ 3𝑠 βˆ’ 3 β‰₯ π‘˜ + 2𝑠 βˆ’ 3, so π’œ is non-empty, and thus β„‹ was not optimal. Finally, we may assume that |𝐻1 ∩ 𝐻2 | ∈ [2, 𝑠 βˆ’ 2]. Then we do the a similar count as for (3.8). The first two steps (with 𝑖2 , 𝑖3 ) are the same. The part with 𝑗𝑖 is, however, slightly modified. Take 𝑗 β€² ∈ (𝐻1 ∩ 𝐻2 ) βˆ– {𝑖3 } and 𝑗 β€²β€² ∈ 𝐻1 βˆ– (𝐻2 βˆͺ {𝑖2 }. Such choices are possible due to |𝐻1 ∩ 𝐻2 | ∈ [2, 𝑠 βˆ’ 2]. Count the sets 𝐹 ∈ β„± such that 𝐹 ∩ {𝑖2 , 𝑖3 , 𝑗 β€² } = 𝑗 β€² . They must intersect 𝐻3 βˆ– {𝑖2 }. Next, crucially, count the sets in 𝐹 ∈ β„± such that 𝐹 ∩ {𝑖2 , 𝑖3 , 𝑗 β€² , 𝑗 β€²β€² } = 𝑗 β€²β€² . They must intersect 𝐻2 βˆ– {𝑖2 , 𝑗 β€² } (note the size of this set is 𝑠 βˆ’ 2 instead of 𝑠 βˆ’ 1). The remaining count is the same: let {𝑗1 , . . . , π‘—π‘ βˆ’4 } := 𝐻1 βˆ– {𝑖2 , 𝑖3 , 𝑗 β€² , 𝑗 β€²β€² } and, for each 𝑙 ∈ [𝑠 βˆ’ 4], count the sets 𝐹 ∈ β„± such that 𝐹 ∩ {𝑖2 , 𝑖3 , 𝑗 β€² , 𝑗 β€²β€² , 𝑗1 , . . . , 𝑗𝑙 } = 𝑗𝑙 . They must additionally intersect either 𝐻2 βˆ– {𝑖2 , 𝑗 β€² }, or 𝐻3 βˆ– {𝑖3 }. Thus, we obtain the following bound.

(3.8)

(οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘šβˆ’1 π‘šβˆ’π‘ βˆ’1 |β„±| ≀ βˆ’ + π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘šβˆ’2 π‘šβˆ’π‘ βˆ’1 βˆ’ + π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘šβˆ’3 π‘šβˆ’π‘ βˆ’2 βˆ’ + π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘šβˆ’4 π‘šβˆ’π‘ βˆ’2 βˆ’ + π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘šβˆ’5 π‘šβˆ’π‘ βˆ’4 βˆ’ + π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 Β·Β·Β· (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘šβˆ’π‘  π‘š βˆ’ 2𝑠 + 1 βˆ’ =: 𝑓 β€² (3). π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2

(οΈ€ )οΈ€ (οΈ€π‘šβˆ’π‘ βˆ’3)οΈ€ (οΈ€ )οΈ€ We have 𝑓 (3) βˆ’ 𝑓 β€² (3) = π‘šβˆ’π‘ βˆ’2 βˆ’ π‘˜βˆ’2 = π‘šβˆ’π‘ βˆ’3 β‰₯ 1 due to π‘š β‰₯ 𝑠 + π‘˜, and thus π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’3 β€² |β„±| ≀ 𝑓 (3) < 𝑓 (3) = |β„±2 (𝑠)|. Thus, in the assumption 𝑠 β‰₯ π‘˜ and if β„‹, |β„‹| β‰₯ 3, is not isomorphic to 𝒯2 (𝑠), we have strict inequality in (3.6) for 𝑧 β€² = 3. The lemma is proven. 

4. Families with fixed covering number and maximum degree proportion One of our main tools for this section is the following structural result due to Dinur and Friedgut [8]. We say that a family π’₯ βŠ‚ 2[𝑛] is a 𝑗-junta, if there exists a subset 𝐽 βŠ‚ [𝑛] of size 𝑗 (the center of the junta), such that the membership of a set in β„± is determined only by its intersection with 𝐽, that is, for some family π’₯ * βŠ‚ 2𝐽 (the defining family) we have β„± = {𝐹 : 𝐹 ∩ 𝐽 ∈ π’₯ * }. Theorem 4.1 ([8]). For any integer(οΈ€π‘Ÿ β‰₯ )οΈ€ 2, there exist functions 𝑗(π‘Ÿ), 𝑐(π‘Ÿ), such that (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’π‘Ÿfor )οΈ€ any [𝑛] integers 1 < 𝑗(π‘Ÿ) < π‘˜ < 𝑛/2, if β„± βŠ‚ π‘˜ is an intersecting family with |β„±| β‰₯ 𝑐(π‘Ÿ) π‘˜βˆ’π‘Ÿ , then there exists an intersecting 𝑗-junta π’₯ with 𝑗 ≀ 𝑗(π‘Ÿ) and (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘›βˆ’π‘Ÿ (4.1) |β„± βˆ– π’₯ | ≀ 𝑐(π‘Ÿ) . π‘˜βˆ’π‘Ÿ 4.1. Proof of Theorem 1.10. Recall the expression of the size of π’ž3 (𝑛, π‘˜), obtained in the proof of Lemma 3.1 (cf. (3.8)): (οΈ‚ |π’ž3 (𝑛, π‘˜)| = 3 +

(4.2)

)οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘›βˆ’2 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 βˆ’ + π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘›βˆ’3 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’2 βˆ’ + π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘›βˆ’4 π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’3 βˆ’ + π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 Β·Β·Β· (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ π‘›βˆ’π‘˜βˆ’1 𝑛 βˆ’ 2π‘˜ βˆ’ . π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2

Let 𝐢 be a sufficiently large constant, which value shall be clear later.10 The case of π‘˜ ≀ 𝐢 follows from the(οΈ€ original result of Frankl. In what follows, we assume that π‘˜ β‰₯ 𝐢. )οΈ€ Take any family β„± βŠ‚ [𝑛] with 𝜏 (β„±) = 3. Theorem 4.1 implies that there(οΈ€ exists 𝐽, π‘˜ )οΈ€ a (οΈ€set )οΈ€ π‘›βˆ’5 π‘›βˆ’5 * [𝐽] |𝐽| ≀ 𝑐(5), and an intersecting family π’₯ βŠ‚ 2 , such that |β„± βˆ– π’₯ | ≀ 𝑗(5) π‘˜βˆ’5 ≀𝐢 π‘˜βˆ’4 , (οΈ€ )οΈ€ where π’₯ := {𝐹 ∈ [𝑛] : 𝐹 ∩ 𝐽 ∈ π’₯ * }. π‘˜ The first step of the proof is to show that π’₯ is, in fact, a dictatorship: π’₯ * consists of one singleton. Indeed, if π’₯ * contains a singleton, then we may as well assume that π’₯ * consists of that only singleton. Otherwise, any set in π’₯ ∩ β„± must intersect 𝐽 in at least 2 elements. Moreover, for any two elements we choose, there is a set in 𝐹 ∈ β„± that does not contain any of those two elements, so any set in π’₯ ∩ β„± must intersect 𝐹 . This gives the bound (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚(︁(οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ |𝐽| π‘›βˆ’2 𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜ βˆ’ 2 )︁ , (4.3) |π’₯ ∩ β„±| ≀ βˆ’ 2 π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 and, given that (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚ (︁(︂𝑛 βˆ’ 2)οΈ‚ (︂𝑛 βˆ’ π‘˜ βˆ’ 2)οΈ‚)︁ 𝑛 βˆ’ |𝐽|2 𝑛 βˆ’ |𝐽|2 βˆ’ π‘˜ + 1 βˆ’ >𝐢 0.99 βˆ’ , π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 π‘˜βˆ’2 we compare (4.3) with (4.2) and get that |π’₯ ∩ β„±| < 21 |π’ž3 (𝑛, π‘˜)| (remark that we also used 2 that (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’5)οΈ€π‘˜ >1𝐢 and thus that the number of lines in (4.2) is bigger than |𝐽| ). Since |β„± βˆ– π’₯ | ≀ < 2 |π’ž3 (𝑛, π‘˜)|, we get that |β„±| < |π’ž3 (𝑛, π‘˜)|. π‘˜βˆ’4 From now on, we may assume that π’₯ is a dictatorship, say, 𝐽 = {1} and π’₯ = {{1}}.11 The next part of the proof will make use of the bipartite switching trick. We shall transform our family β„± into another family (denoted by β„± β€²β€² ), which will satisfy 𝜏 (β„± β€²β€² ) = 3, |β„± β€²β€² | β‰₯ |β„±| (with 10We 11We

use a subscript β€œπΆβ€ in the inequalities, i.e., β‰₯𝐢 , in which we need that 𝐢 is sufficiently large. note that the remaining part of the argument works for any 𝑛 > 2π‘˜ β‰₯ 8.

strict equality in case β„± β€² is not isomorphic to β„±) and, moreover, β„± β€²β€² (Β―1) will have covering number 2 and a much cleaner structure. To that end, take any β„³ = {𝑀1 , . . . , 𝑀𝑧 } βŠ‚ β„± β€² (Β―1) such that 𝜏 (β„³) = 2 and β„³ is minimal w.r.t. this property. Remark that 𝑧 β‰₯ 3 due to the fact that 𝜏 (β„³) = 2 and β„³ is intersecting. The next part of the proof borrows notations and ideas of Theorem 2.4. For each 𝑙 (οΈ€βˆˆ [𝑧], )οΈ€ we can find 𝑖𝑙 as in (3.3). W.l.o.g., assume that {𝑖1 , . . . , 𝑖𝑧 } = [2, 𝑧 + 1]. Since |β„±(Β―1)| ≀ π‘›βˆ’5 , we π‘˜βˆ’4 β€² β€² may apply the same exchange argument via 𝐺𝑖 as in Theorem 2.4 and get a family β„± , such that β„± β€² (Β―1) = β„³βˆͺ𝒰, where 𝒰 contains only sets that contain [2, 𝑧 +1], and β„±(1) consists of all sets intersecting all sets in β„± β€² (Β―1). We repeat the same exchange with any element contained in all but at one set from β„³. At the end, we may assume that each π‘ˆ ∈ 𝒰 contains [2, 𝑑′ ] for 𝑑′ β‰₯ 𝑧 + 1. As in the proof of Theorem 2.4, we get |β„± β€² | > |β„±| unless β„± β€² is isomorphic to β„± (recall that π‘˜ β‰₯ 𝐢 by assumption). If β„³ is isomorphic to 𝒯2 (π‘˜) (cf. (1.7)), then the number of the elements contained in exactly two sets (all but one sets) is π‘˜ + 1, and thus we may immediately conclude that 𝒰 = βˆ…: no π‘˜-set can contain a subset of size π‘˜ + 1. Otherwise, β„³ is not isomorphic to 𝒯2 (π‘˜).12 Let us show that we may assume that 𝒰 is empty. As we have said, it is clear if 𝑑′ β‰₯ π‘˜ + 2. Otherwise, consider the family β„³β€² := {𝑀 βˆ– [2, 𝑑′ ] : 𝑀 ∈ β„³} and note that sets in β„³β€² have size at least 1. If there is no element 𝑖′ ∈ [𝑑′ + 1, 𝑛] that is contained in at least 2 sets of β„³β€² , then take two elements 𝑖 ∈ 𝑀 β€² and 𝑗 ∈ 𝑀 β€²β€² , where 𝑑′ + 1 ≀ 𝑖 < 𝑗 ≀ 𝑛 and 𝑀 β€² , 𝑀 β€²β€² are distinct sets in β„³β€² , and perform the (𝑖, 𝑗)-shift on β„± β€² . It is easy to see that 𝜏 (𝑆𝑖𝑗 (β„³)) = 2, moreover, is 𝑆𝑖𝑗 (β„±) is intersecting. Thus, we may replace β„± β€² with 𝑆𝑖𝑗 (β„± β€² ) and β„³ with 𝑆𝑖𝑗 (β„³). Next, we can assume that there is an element in 𝑖′ ∈ [𝑑′ + 1, 𝑛] that is contained in at least 2 sets of β„³β€² . Now we may reuse the argument of Theorem 1.7 again. Consider the last exchange graph from the proof of Theorem 1.7, i.e., 𝐺(𝑑′ , 𝐼), where 𝐼 is formed as follows. We include 𝑖′ in 𝐼, as well as one element from each of the sets from β„³β€² that do not contain 𝑖′ . We have |𝐼| ≀ 𝑧 βˆ’ 1. (Note that, as before, some elements we chose may coincide, making the last inequality strict.) In terms of the proof of Theorem 1.7, we have 𝑧 β€² = |𝐼| + 1 ≀ 𝑧 ≀ 𝑑′ βˆ’ 1 = 𝑧 β€²β€² . Moreover, by the choice of 𝐼, we have |β„³ ∩ 𝒫𝑏 (𝑑′ , 𝐼)| = βˆ…. Therefore, we can perform the exchange operations as before for all possible choices of 𝐼, concluding that either all sets in 𝒰 must contain 𝑖′ , or they must contain some fixed set 𝑀 β€² ∈ β„³β€² . The latter is, however, impossible, since it would again imply that a π‘˜-element set from 𝒰 contains a (β‰₯ π‘˜ + 1)-element set 𝑀 β€² βˆͺ [2, 𝑑′ ]. Therefore, we may assume that all sets in 𝒰 contain 𝑖′ , and thus all contain [2, 𝑑′ ] βˆͺ {𝑖′ }. Finally, we may perform exactly the same exchange operations as in the proof of Theorem 2.4, but with [2, 𝑑′ ] replaced by [2, 𝑑′ ] βˆͺ {𝑖′ } in the definition π’«π‘Ž (𝑑′ , 𝐼) and 𝒫𝑏 (𝑑′ , 𝐼) (denoted by π’«π‘Žβ€² (𝑑′ , 𝐼) and 𝒫𝑏′ (𝑑′ , 𝐼), respectively). The reason it will work now is the extra fixed element in 𝒫𝑏′ (𝑑′ , 𝐼), which makes the number of fixed elements in 𝒫𝑏′ (𝑑′ , 𝐼) at least as big as in π’«π‘Žβ€² (𝑑′ , 𝐼). After the switches, we obtain a family β„± β€²β€² , which is intersecting, satisfies |β„± β€²β€² | β‰₯ |β„±| and β„± β€²β€² (Β―1) = β„³. Moreover, it is easy to see that 𝜏 (β„± β€²β€² ) = 3. Finally, we need to show that, among all minimal families, the choice of 𝒯2 (π‘˜) is the unique optimal. But this is a direct application of the second part of Lemma 3.1 with 𝑠 = π‘˜ and [2, 𝑛] playing the role of [π‘š]. Note that 𝑛 > 2π‘˜, and π‘š β‰₯ 2π‘˜. The proof of Theorem 1.10 is complete.

12This

is only needed for the uniqueness of the extremal family π’ž3 (𝑛, π‘˜), since some of the exchanges we shall perform below may not necessarily strictly increase the size. But this does not pose problems since we will eventually arrive at a family β„± β€²β€² with β„± β€²β€² (Β―1) = β„³, which we will show to have strictly smaller size than that of π’ž3 (𝑛, π‘˜).

4.2. Proof of Theorem 1.12. Let 𝐢 be a sufficiently large constant, which value shall be clear later.13 The case of π‘˜ ≀ 𝐢 follows from the original result of Frankl. In what follows, we assume that π‘˜ β‰₯ 𝐢. First of all, we remark that π’Ÿ3/7 satisfies the condition of the theorem, since βˆ†(π’Ÿ3/7 ) = 73 + 𝑂( π‘›π‘˜ ) π‘›βˆ’3 , we get 𝑑𝑖 (β„±) β‰₯ 12 |β„±| 1 βˆ’ π‘›π‘˜ , which is bigger than 𝑐|β„±| π‘˜βˆ’3 * for 𝑛 > π‘˜/πœ–,(οΈ€ a)οΈ€contradiction. }οΈ€ sets of size at least 3. Let us put {οΈ€ Thus, (οΈ€[𝑛])οΈ€ π’₯ contains only [𝑛] * * * π’₯3 := π’₯ ∩ 3 and π’₯3 := 𝐹 ∈ π‘˜ : 𝐹 ∩ 𝐽 ∈ π’₯3 . Recall that a fractional covering number 𝜏 * (𝒒) of a family 𝒒 βŠ‚ 2[𝑛] is the minimum value βˆ‘οΈ€ βˆ‘οΈ€ of 𝑛𝑖=1 𝑀𝑖 , where 0 ≀ 𝑀𝑖 ≀ 1 are real numbers, such that π‘–βˆˆπΊ 𝑀𝑖 β‰₯ 1 for each 𝐺 ∈ 𝒒. Note that if we allow 𝑀𝑖 to take integer values only, then we get back to the definition of covering number. Clearly, 𝜏 (𝒒) β‰₯ 𝜏 * (𝒒). Arguing as above, we have 𝜏 * (π’₯3* ) > 2. Indeed, it is easy to see that, for any family 𝒒, * βˆ†(𝒒) β‰₯ |𝒒|/𝜏 * (𝒒). Therefore, if 𝜏 (π’₯3* ) ≀ 2βƒ’ then, of βƒ’ course, 𝜏 (π’₯3 ∩ β„±) ≀ 2 and so at least 1βƒ’ one element 𝑖 ∈ 𝐽 satisfies 𝑑𝑖 (β„± ∩ π’₯3 ) β‰₯ 2 β„± ∩ π’₯3 βƒ’. Since the vast majority of sets from β„± are actually from β„± ∩ π’₯3 (due to (4.4)), we again get 𝑑𝑖 (β„±) (οΈ€[𝑛]> )οΈ€ 𝑐|β„±|, a contradiction. FΒ¨ uredi [29] showed that, for an intersecting family 𝒒 βŠ‚ 𝑝 , we have 𝜏 * (𝒒) ≀ 𝑝 βˆ’ 1 + 1/𝑝, and, moreover, if 𝒒 is not a projective plane of order 𝑝 βˆ’ 1, then 𝜏 * (𝒒) ≀ 𝑝 βˆ’ 1. Thus, since 𝜏 * (π’₯3* ) > 2, it must be isomorphic to the Fano plane 𝒫. In what follows, we assume that π’₯3* = 𝒫. It is not difficult to check by simple case analysis that any set intersecting all sets in 𝒫 must actually contain a set from 𝒫. Thus,⋃︀we get that π’₯ * βŠ‚ {𝑆 βŠ‚ 𝐽 : 𝑃 βŠ‚ 𝑆 for some 𝑃 ∈ 𝒫}. We thus may also assume that 𝐽 = 𝑃 βˆˆπ’« 𝑃 = [7] and π’₯ = π’Ÿ3/7 . Summarizing the discussion above, we may assume that the junta that approximates β„± is isomorphic to π’Ÿ3/7 . The last step is to show that β„± is actually isomorphic to π’Ÿ3/7 . Assume that β„± β€² := β„± βˆ– π’₯ * is non-empty. Then, for each 𝐹 ∈ β„± β€² , there exists 𝑃 ∈ 𝒫 such that 𝐹 ∩ 𝑃 = βˆ…. For each 𝑃 ∈ 𝒫, put (οΈ‚ )οΈ‚}︁ {︁ [𝑛] π’₯ (𝑃 ) := 𝐹 : 𝑃 βŠ‚ 𝐹 ∈ , π‘˜ β„±(𝑃 ) := π’₯ (𝑃 ) ∩ β„±, {οΈ€ }οΈ€ β„± β€² (𝑃 ) := 𝐹 : 𝐹 ∈ β„± β€² , 𝐹 ∩ 𝑃 = βˆ… . Then β„±(𝑃 ) and β„± β€² (𝑃 ) are cross-intersecting, moreover, the former is)οΈ€(π‘˜ βˆ’ 3)-uniform, (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’5)οΈ€ family (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’7 β€² while the second one is π‘˜-uniform and satisfies |β„± (𝑃 )| ≀ πœ– π‘˜βˆ’4 ≀𝐢 π‘˜βˆ’4 . Thus, we can apply (2.9) with π‘˜ βˆ’ 3, π‘˜ and 𝑛 βˆ’ 3 playing the roles of π‘Ž, 𝑏 and 𝑛, respectively, and get that replacing β„±(𝑃 ) βˆͺ β„± β€² (𝑃 ) with π’₯ (𝑃 ) in β„± will strictly increase the size of β„± (given that it was not there in the first place). Repeating this for each 𝑃 ∈ 𝒫, we transform β„± into π’Ÿ3/7 . Moreover, if there was some change made in the process, then |β„±| < |π’Ÿ3/7 |. Thus, we conclude that β„± is isomorphic to π’Ÿ3/7 . 13As

in the proof of Theorem 1.10, we use a subscript β€œπΆβ€ in the inequalities, in which we need that 𝐢 is sufficiently large.

5. Conclusion (οΈ€ )οΈ€ In this paper, we found the largest intersecting family β„± βŠ‚ [𝑛] with 𝜏 (β„±) β‰₯ 3, provided π‘˜ 𝑛 > πΆπ‘˜ for some absolute constant 𝐢. Actually, we proved more than that. Provided that (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’5)οΈ€ 𝛾(β„±) ≀ π‘˜βˆ’4 and 𝜏 (β„±) β‰₯ 3, we showed that |β„±| ≀ |π’ž3 (𝑛, π‘˜)|, with equality only if β„± is isomorphic to π’ž3 (𝑛, π‘˜), for (οΈ€ any )οΈ€ 𝑛 > 2π‘˜ β‰₯ 8. With some effort, we can replace the condition on diversity by 𝛾(β„±) < π‘›βˆ’4 . However, since we use juntas result to show that the diversity π‘˜βˆ’3 of any extremal β„± must be small, the condition 𝑛 > πΆπ‘˜, π‘˜ > 𝐢 is necessary for our approach. This motivates the following problem. Problem 1. Determine 𝑐(𝑛, π‘˜, 3) for all 𝑛 > 2π‘˜. We believe that the family π’ž3 (𝑛, π‘˜) should be extremal for all 𝑛 > 2π‘˜ β‰₯ 10. What can one say about 𝑐(𝑛, π‘˜, 𝑑) for 𝑑 β‰₯ 4? Using juntas, (οΈ€one can )οΈ€ similarly show that the largest family must have very small diversity (say, at most π‘›βˆ’2𝑑 ) for 𝑛 > 𝐢(𝑑)π‘˜. Using π‘˜βˆ’2𝑑 similar proof logic, this allows to deduce the result of [23] for 𝑛 > πΆπ‘˜ 4 . The main difficulty (at least for 𝑛 > πΆπ‘˜ 𝑑 ) for 𝑑 β‰₯ 5 lies in the following problem. Problem 2. Given an intersecting family β„± of π‘˜-sets with 𝜏 (β„±) = 𝑑, what is the maximum number of hitting sets of size 𝑑 it may have? Finally, we state the following question: (οΈ€ )οΈ€ Problem 3. What is the maximum of 𝛾(β„±) for intersecting β„± βŠ‚ [𝑛] ? π‘˜ (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’3)οΈ€ I showed in [41] that 𝛾(β„±) ≀ π‘˜βˆ’2 for 𝑛 > πΆπ‘˜ with some absolute constant 𝐢. In particular, this makes Theorem 2.3 complete: in that range, it covers all possible values of diversity. Following Frankl, I conjectured that the same bound should √ hold for 𝑛 β‰₯ 3π‘˜, however, a counterexample was provided by Huang [34] for 𝑛 ≀ (2 + 3)π‘˜. I still believe that (οΈ€π‘›βˆ’3)οΈ€ 𝛾(β„±) ≀ π‘˜βˆ’2 should hold for moderately large 𝑛, say, for 𝑛 β‰₯ 5π‘˜. The case of smaller 𝑛 is also very interesting. Acknowledgements: I would like to thank Peter Frankl for introducing me to the area and for numerous interesting discussions we had on the topic. References [1] A. Arman and T. Retter, An upper bound for the size of a k-uniform intersecting family with covering number k, J. Comb. Theory Ser. A 147 (2017), 18–26. [2] A. BjΒ¨ orner and G. Kalai, An extended Euler-PoincarΒ΄e theorem, Acta Math. 161 (1988), N1, 279–303. [3] B. BollobΒ΄ as, On generalized graphs, Acta Math. Acad. Sci. Hungar 16 (1965), 447–452. [4] B. BollobΒ΄ as and A. Thomason, Threshold functions, Combinatorica 7 (1986) 35–38. [5] D. D. Cherkashin, On hypergraph cliques with chromatic number 3, Moscow J. Comb. Numb. Th. 1 (2011), N3. [6] S. Das and T. Tran, Removal and Stability for Erd˝ os–Ko–Rado, SIAM J. Disc. Math. 30 (2016), 1102β€” 1114. [7] M. Deza and P. Frankl, Erd˝ os–Ko–Rado Theorem β€” 22 Years Later, SIAM J. Algebraic Discrete Methods 4 (1983), N4, 419–431. [8] I. Dinur, E. Friedgut, Intersecting families are essentially contained in juntas, Comb. Probab. Comput. 18 (2009), 107–122. [9] D. Ellis, N. Keller and N. Lifshitz, Stability versions of ErdΒ‚osβ€”Ko-–Rado type theorems, via isoperimetry (2016), arXiv:1604.02160 [10] P. Erd˝ os, Problems and results in combinatorial analysis, ThΒ΄eorie Combinatorie, Colloq. int. Roma 2 (1973), Acad. Naz. Lincei, Roma (1976), 3–17. [11] P. Erd˝ os, C. Ko, R. Rado, Intersection theorems for systems of finite sets, The Quarterly Journal of Mathematics, 12 (1961), N1, 313–320. [12] P. Erd˝ os, L. LovΒ΄ asz, Problems and results on 3-chromatic hypergraphs and some related questions, in: Infnite and Finite Sets, Proc. Colloq. Math. Soc. JΒ΄anos Bolyai, Keszthely, Hungary (1973), NorthHolland, Amsterdam (1974), 609–627.

[13] [14] [15] [16] [17] [18] [19] [20] [21] [22] [23] [24] [25] [26] [27] [28] [29] [30] [31] [32] [33] [34] [35] [36] [37] [38] [39] [40] [41] [42] [43]

C. Feghali, Multiply Erd˝ os–Ko–Rado Theorem (2017), arXiv:1712.09942. P. Frankl, On intersecting families of finite sets, J. Comb. Theory Ser. A 24 (1978), N2, 146–161. P. Frankl, On intersecting families of finite sets, Bull. Austral. Math. Soc. 21 (1980), 363β€”372. P. Frankl, Erd˝ os–Ko–Rado theorem with conditions on the maximal degree, J. Comb. Theory Ser. A 46 (1987), N2, 252–263. P. Frankl, Antichains of fixed diameter, Moscow J. Comb. Numb. Th. 7 (2017), N3. P. Frankl, A near exponential improvement on a bound of Erd˝ os and LovΒ΄ asz, preprint, https://users. renyi.hu/~pfrankl/2017-4.pdf P. Frankl, J. Han, H. Huang, Y. Zhao A degree version of the Hilton–Milner theorem, J. Comb. Theory Ser. A 155 (2018), 493–502. P. Frankl, A. Kupavskii, Counting intersecting and pairs of cross-intersecting families, Comb. Probab. Comput. 27 (2018), N1, 60–68. P. Frankl, A. Kupavskii, Erd˝ os–Ko–Rado theorem for {0, Β±1}-vectors, J. Comb. Theory Ser. A 155 (2018), 157–1792. P. Frankl, M. Matsumoto, I. Ruzsa and N. Tokushige, Minimum shadows in uniform hypergraphs and a generalization of the Takagi function, J. Comb. Theory Ser. A 69 (1995), 125–148. P. Frankl, K. Ota and N. Tokushige, Uniform intersecting families with covering number four, J. Comb. Theory Ser. A 71 (1995), 127–145. P. Frankl, K. Ota and N. Tokushige, Covers in uniform intersecting families and a counterexample to a conjecture of LovΒ΄ asz, J. Comb. Theory Ser. A 74 (1996), 33–42. P. Frankl, N. Tokushige, Some best possible inequalities concerning cross-intersecting families, J. Comb. Theory Ser. A 61 (1992), N1, 87–97. P. Frankl, N. Tokushige, A note on Huang–Zhao theorem on intersecting families with large minimum degree, Discrete Mathematics 340 (2016), N5, 1098–1103. P. Frankl and N. Tokushige, Invitation to intersection problems for finite sets, J. Comb. Theory Ser. A 144 (2016), 157–211. E. Friedgut, On the measure of intersecting families, uniqueness and stability, Combinatorica, 28 (2008), 503–528. Z. FΒ¨ uredi, Erd˝ os–Ko–Rado type theorems with upper bounds on the maximum degree, Colloquia Math. Soc. J. Bolyai 25 (1978), Szeged, 177–207. Z. FΒ¨ uredi, Maximum degree and fractional matchings in uniform hypergraphs, Combinatorica 1 (1981), N2, 155–162. J. Han, Y. Kohayakawa, The maximum size of a non-trivial intersecting uniform family that is not a subfamily of the Hilton–Milner family, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 145 (2017) N1, 73–87. H. HΒ΄ an, Y. Person, M. Schacht, On perfect matchings in uniform hypergraphs with large minimum vertex degree, SIAM J. Disc. Math. 23 (2009), N2, 732–748. A.J.W. Hilton, E.C. Milner, Some intersection theorems for systems of finite sets, Quart. J. Math. Oxford 18 (1967), 369–384. H. Huang, Two extremal problems on intersecting families (2018), arXiv:1804.11269 H. Huang and Y. Zhao, Degree versions of the Erd˝ os–Ko–Rado theorem and Erd˝ os hypergraph matching conjecture, J. Comb. Theory Ser. A 150 (2017), 233–247. to appear F. Ihringer, A. Kupavskii, Regular intersecting families (2017), arXiv:1709.10462 G. Katona, A theorem of finite sets, β€œTheory of Graphs, Proc. Coll. Tihany, 1966”, Akad, Kiado, Budapest, 1968; Classic Papers in Combinatorics (1987), 381–401. N. Keller, N. Lifshitz, The junta method for hypergraphs and the Erd˝ os-ChvΒ΄ atal simplex conjecture (2017), arXiv:1707.02643 A. Kostochka, Dhruv Mubayi, The structure of large intersecting families Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 145 (2017), N6, 2311–2321. J.B. Kruskal, The Number of Simplices in a Complex, Mathematical optimization techniques 251 (1963), 251–278. A. Kupavskii, Diversity of intersecting families, European Journal of Combinatorics 74 (2018), 39–47. A. Kupavskii, Degree versions, preprint A. Kupavskii, D. Zakharov, Regular bipartite graphs and intersecting families, J. Comb. Theory Ser. A 155 (2018), 180–189.

University of Birmingham, Moscow Institute of Physics and Technology; Email: [email protected].